Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Once Again on the *Hetucakraḍamaru: Rotating the Wheels.Huanhuan He & Leonard W. J. van der Kuijp - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (2):267-302.
    The little versified treatise on the elements of Buddhist logic, often referred to as the Hetucakraḍamaru, is usually attributed to Dignāga. It is only available in a Tibetan translation and quotations from a few of its verses are extant in Sanskrit sources. On the basis of a novel interpretation that is based on a critical edition of the text, we argue that there is a good reason why its title was Hetucakraḍamaru - a ḍamaru is a two-headed drum. The “heads” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic in Classical Indian Philosophy.Brendan Gillon - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • History, philology, and the philosophical study of sanskrit texts.Parimal G. Patil - 2010 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 38 (2):163-202.
    This paper is a critical review of Jonardan Ganeri’s Philosophy in Classical India.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Logic, Scripture, and Hermeneutics in Zhencheng’s Critique of the Thesis of No-motion.Chen-kuo Lin - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (4):811-829.
    This paper examines the philosophical debate on Seng Zhao ’s Thesis on No-Motion of Things, a debate which took place approximately at the turn of the late sixteenth and the early seventeenth centuries. Without doubt the Zhao Treatise is the most precious gem in the early Chinese Madhyamaka legacy. The sterling reputation of this seminal treatise had never been challenged until Zhencheng published the Logical Investigation of the Thesis of No-Motion of Things during 1588–1589. The following focuses on Zhencheng’s WBQZLL (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Way of Nonacquisition: Jizang's Philosophy of Ontic Indeterminacy.Chien-Hsing Ho - 2014 - In Chen-Kuo Lin & Michael Radich (eds.), A Distant Mirror: Articulating Indic Ideas in Sixth and Seventh Century Chinese Buddhism. Hamburg University Press. pp. 397-418.
    For Jizang (549−623), a prominent philosophical exponent of Chinese Madhyamaka, all things are empty of determinate form or nature. Given anything X, no linguistic item can truly and conclusively be applied to X in the sense of positing a determinate form or nature therein. This philosophy of ontic indeterminacy is connected closely with his notion of the Way (dao), which seems to indicate a kind of ineffable principle of reality. However, Jizang also equates the Way with nonacquisition as a conscious (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The concept of paksa in indian logic.J. F. Staal - 1972 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 2 (2):156-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Buddhist Epistemology and the Liar Paradox.Szymon Bogacz - 2024 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 102 (1):206-220.
    The liar paradox is still an open philosophical problem. Most contemporary answers to the paradox target the logical principles underlying the reasoning from the liar sentence to the paradoxical conclusion that the liar sentence is both true and false. In contrast to these answers, Buddhist epistemology offers resources to devise a distinctively epistemological approach to the liar paradox. In this paper, I mobilise these resources and argue that the liar sentence is what Buddhist epistemologists call a contradiction with one’s own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Existence and non-existence in haribhadra sūri's anekānta-jaya-patākā.Frank Van Den Bossche - 1995 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (4):429-468.
    InPart I of my article I have tried to show how the problem of negation has led the Jains to accept Non-existence and Existence as constituents ordharmas of every real object and to formulate their first dialectical principle:sad-asad-rŪpa $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{m} $$ vastu or ‘Every real object possesses a mode as an existent and as a non-existent’. Their interpretation of negation seems to be based on the ‘primitive’ realistic standpoint that every word in a true proposition, including the word ‘not(-)’, must have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bhāvaviveka's prajñāpradīpa.William L. Ames - 1993 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 21 (3):209-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Principle of Reductio ad Absurdum Against a Comparative Background.Janusz Chmielewski - 1978 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 8:138-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Buddhist Argumentation.Tom J. F. Tillemans - 2008 - Argumentation 22 (1):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The eastern side of the circle: the contribution of Mikhail Tubjanskij.Craig Brandist - 2015 - Studies in East European Thought 67 (3-4):209-228.
    The intellectual biography of M. I. Tubjanskij is considered, setting his work within the context of the Bakhtin Circle in the mid-1920s, but considering his wider engagement with the intellectual field of the time. Tubjanskij’s passage from studies of the work of Hermann Cohen and of Plato, through his work on Buddhism, contemporary Bengali thought, especially the work of Rabindranath Tagore, to his later work on Mongolian culture is described and analysed. In conclusion it is argued that the non-European orientation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dinnāga's views on reasoning (svārthānumāna).Richard P. Hayes - 1980 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 8 (3):219-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Non-existent Things as Subject of Inference in Bhāviveka’s Dacheng Zhangzhen Lun.Lai Yan Fong - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (4):795-810.
    This paper is a preliminary study of Bhāviveka’s Svātantrika-Mādhyamika justifications for taking non-existent things as the subject of an inference, based on his Dacheng Zhangzhen Lun. Bhāviveka’s treatment of inference is similar to that of Dignāga in that the subject is required to be existent. Bhāviveka also holds that, in a conventional sense, words refer to universals and to the existent entities that possess them, while the two are cognised together. However, in his inference for the unreality of unconditioned things, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On whether the buddhist 'syllogism' (par rth num na) is a Sui generis inference.Douglas D. Daye - 1991 - Asian Philosophy 1 (2):175 – 183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ancient indian logic as a theory of non-monotonic reasoning.Claus Oetke - 1996 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (5):447-539.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Indian logic revisited: Nyāyapra veśa reviewed. [REVIEW]Brendan S. Gillon & Martha Lile Love - 1980 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 8 (4):349-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some logical issues in madhyamaka thought.Brian Galloway - 1989 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 17 (1):1-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Bh?vaviveka's Praj�?prad?pa.William L. Ames - 1994 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (2):93-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations