Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kidnapped: The Ethics of Paying Ransoms.Jeffrey W. Howard - 2017 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 35 (4):675-688.
    Should governments pay ransoms to terrorist organisations that unjustly kidnap their citizens? The United Kingdom and the United States refuse to negotiate with terrorist groups that kidnap and threaten to kill their people. In contrast, continental European countries, such as France and Germany, have regularly paid ransoms to rescue hostages. Who is right? This debate has raged in the public domain in recent years, but no sustained attempt has been made to subject the matter to philosophical scrutiny. This article explores (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Bioethics Needs a Disability Moral Psychology.Joseph A. Stramondo - 2016 - Hastings Center Report 46 (3):22-30.
    The deeply entrenched, sometimes heated conflict between the disability movement and the profession of bioethics is well known and well documented. Critiques of prenatal diagnosis and selective abortion are probably the most salient and most sophisticated of disability studies scholars’ engagements with bioethics, but there are many other topics over which disability activists and scholars have encountered the field of bioethics in an adversarial way, including health care rationing, growth-attenuation interventions, assisted reproduction technology, and physician-assisted suicide. -/- The tension between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Acts, intentions, and moral permissibility: in defence of the doctrine of double effect.W. J. FitzPatrick - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):317-321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Intend/Foresee Distinction and the Problem of “Closeness”.William J. Fitzpatrick - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):585-617.
    The distinction between harm that is intended as a means or end, and harm that is merely a foreseen side-effect of one’s action, is widely cited as a significant factor in a variety of ethical contexts. Many use it, for example, to distinguish terrorist acts from certain acts of war that may have similar results as side-effects. Yet Bennett and others have argued that its application is so arbitrary that if it can be used to cast certain harmful actions in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Priority and Posteriority of Right.Jon Garthoff - 2015 - Theoria 81 (3):222-248.
    In this article I articulate two pairs of theses about the relationship between the right and the good and I sketch an account of morality that systematically vindicates all four theses, despite a nearly universal consensus that they are not all true. In the first half I elucidate and motivate the theses and explain why leading ethical theorists maintain that at least one of them is false; in the second half I present the outlines of an account of the relationship (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Disambiguating Clinical Intentions: The Ethics of Palliative Sedation.L. A. Jansen - 2010 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35 (1):19-31.
    It is often claimed that the intentions of physicians are multiple, ambiguous, and uncertain—at least with respect to end-of-life care. This claim provides support for the conclusion that the principle of double effect is of little or no value as a guide to end-of-life pain management. This paper critically discusses this claim. It argues that proponents of the claim fail to distinguish two different senses of “intention,” and that, as a result, they are led to exaggerate the extent to which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Acts, intentions, and moral permissibility: In defence of the doctrine of double effect.William J. FitzPatrick - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):317–321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Political Anti-Intentionalism.Matthias Brinkmann - 2018 - Res Publica 24 (2):159-179.
    There has been little debate in political philosophy about whether the intentions of governments matter to the legitimacy of their policies. This paper fills this gap. First, I provide a rigorous statement of political anti-intentionalism, the view that intentions do not matter to political legitimacy. I do so by building on analogous debates in moral philosophy. Second, I sketch some strategies to defend political anti-intentionalism, which I argue are promising and available to a wide range of theories of legitimacy. Third, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Counting Cases of Termination of Life without Request: New Dances with Data.Govert den Hartogh - 2020 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 29 (3):395-402.
    This paper explores the common argument proposed by opponents of the legalization of euthanasia that permitting ending a patient’s life at their request will lead to the eventual legalization of terminating life without request. The author’s examination of data does not support the conclusion that a causal connection exists between legalizing ending of life on request and an increase in the number of cases without request.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Clinicians’ Perspectives on the Duty to Inform Patients About Medical Aid-in-Dying.Elizabeth R. Brassfield & Mara Buchbinder - 2020 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 11 (1):53-62.
    As of 2019, ten jurisdictions in the United States—Oregon, Washington, Montana, Vermont, California, Colorado, the District of Columbia, Hawaii, New Jersey, and Maine—have authorized physicians to...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thomson's Trolley Switch.Robert Shaver - 2011 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 5 (2):1-6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Comments on Doug Husak: The Low Cost of Recognizing (and of Ignoring) the Limited Relevance of Intentions to Permissibility.Alec Walen - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (1):71-78.
    Doug Husak frames a worry that makes sense in the abstract, but in reality, there is not much to worry about. The thesis that intentions are irrelevant to permissibility (IIP) is a straw man. There are reasons to think that the moral significance of intentions is not properly registered in criminal law. But the moral basis for criticism is not nearly as extreme as the IIP, and the fixes are not that hard to make. Lastly, if they are not made, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The act—omission doctrine and negative rights.Ingmar Persson - 2007 - Journal of Value Inquiry 41 (1):15-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations