Switch to: References

Citations of:

Censure and Sanctions

Law and Philosophy 15 (4):407-415 (1996)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Risk-Based Sentencing and Predictive Accuracy.Jesper Ryberg - 2020 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 23 (1):251-263.
    The use of risk assessment tools has come to play an increasingly important role in sentencing decisions in many jurisdictions. A key issue in the theoretical discussion of risk assessment concerns the predictive accuracy of such tools. For instance, it has been underlined that most risk assessment instruments have poor to moderate accuracy in most applications. However, the relation between, on the one hand, judgements of the predictive accuracy of a risk assessment tool and, on the other, conclusions concerning the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Legitimacy of Judicial Responses to Moral Panic: Perceived vs. Normative Legitimacy.Miriam Gur-Arye - 2018 - Criminal Justice Ethics 37 (2):141-163.
    In some instances, the criminal justice system is affected by a moral panic; that is, by an exaggerated social reaction to an assumed threat to moral values. When influenced by moral panic, courts...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neuroscience and Punishment: From Theory to Practice.Allan McCay & Jeanette Kennett - 2019 - Neuroethics 14 (Suppl 3):269-280.
    In a 2004 paper, Greene and Cohen predicted that neuroscience would revolutionise criminal justice by presenting a mechanistic view of human agency that would change people’s intuitions about retributive punishment. According to their theory, this change in intuitions would in turn lead to the demise of retributivism within criminal justice systems. Their influential paper has been challenged, most notably by Morse, who has argued that it is unlikely that there will be major changes to criminal justice systems in response to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rehabilitating Self-Sacrifice: Care Ethics and the Politics of Resistance.Amanda Cawston & Alfred Archer - 2018 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 26 (3):456-477.
    How should feminists view acts of self-sacrifice performed by women? According to a long-standing critique of care ethics such acts ought to be viewed with scepticism. Care ethics, it is claimed, celebrates acts of self-sacrifice on the part of carers and in doing so encourages women to choose caring for others over their own self-development. In doing so, care ethics frustrates attempts to liberate women from the oppression of patriarchy. Care ethicists have responded to this critique by noting limits on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Retributivist Justice in an Unjust Society.Okeoghene Odudu - 2003 - Ratio Juris 16 (3):416-431.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The role of criminal record in the federal sentencing guidelines.Julian V. Roberts - 1994 - Criminal Justice Ethics 13 (1):21-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Punishment.Hugo Adam Bedau - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Retributivism and the Dynamic Desert Model: Three Challenges to Dagan and Roberts.Jesper Ryberg - 2021 - Criminal Justice Ethics 40 (1):56-67.
    A traditional assumption in retributivist thinking is the view that an offender's desert is determined exclusively on the basis of the gravity of the crime committed. However, this assumption has r...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Retributivism and Public Opinion: On the Context Sensitivity of Desert.Göran Duus-Otterström - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (1):125-142.
    Retributivism may seem wholly uninterested in the fit between penal policy and public opinion, but on one rendition of the theory, here called ‘popular retributivism,’ deserved punishments are constituted by the penal conventions of the community. This paper makes two claims against this view. First, the intuitive appeal of popular retributivism is undermined once we distinguish between context sensitivity and convention sensitivity about desert. Retributivism in general can freely accept context sensitivity without being committed to the stronger notion of convention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Enduring Pertinence of the Basic Principle of Retribution☆.Vincent Geeraets - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (4):293-314.
    Many philosophers and legal scholars believe that the principle of retribution can be employed as a basis for respecting the offender as a person and for imposing relatively soft sentences. This belief is inspired, at least to a certain extent, by the penal philosophy of Kant and Hegel. My aim in this article is to question this widely held belief, with my contention being that retributivists locate the basis of these normative considerations in the wrong place. It is not the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Enduring Pertinence of the Basic Principle of Retribution☆.Vincent Geeraets - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (4):293-314.
    Ratio Juris, Volume 34, Issue 4, Page 293-314, December 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Should neurotechnological treatments offered to offenders always be in their best interests?Thomas Søbirk Petersen - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (1):32-36.
    The paper critically discusses the moral view that neurotechnological behavioural treatment for criminal offenders should only be offered if it is in their best interests. First, I show that it is difficult to apply and assess the notion of the offender's best interests unless one has a clear idea of what ‘best interests’ means. Second, I argue that if one accepts that harmful punishment of offenders has a place in the criminal justice system, it seems inconsistent not to accept the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two Ways of Thinking About the Value of Deserved Punishment.Richard L. Lippke - 2019 - The Journal of Ethics 23 (4):387-406.
    Numerous retributivists hold that deserved punishment has intrinsic value. A number of puzzles regarding that claim are identified and discussed. An alternative, more Kantian account of intrinsic value is then identified and the ways in which legal punishment might be understood to cohere with it are explored. That account focuses on the various ways in which legal punishment might be persons-respecting. It is then argued that this Kantian account enables us to solve or evade the puzzles generated by the other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Punishment: Nonconsequentialism.David Wood - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (6):470-482.
    A companion to ‘Punishment: Consequentialism’, and also ‘Punishment: The Future’, this paper examines various nonconsequentialist attempts to justify punishment, that is, attempts that appeal to claims concerning the innate worth or intrinsic character of punishment, quite apart from any consequential good or benefit punishment may be thought to produce. The paper starts with retributive theories, and turns then to the denunciation and expressive theories, before considering combined communicative–retributive theories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Collective Agents and Communicative Theories of Punishment.Bill Wringe - 2012 - Journal of Social Philosophy 43 (4):436-456.
    This paper considers the applicability of expressive theories of punishment to the punishment of corporate entities. The author argues that although arguments which suggest that the denunciatory account is superior to a communicative account in paradigmatic cases of punishment cannot be transferred straightforwardly to cover this kind of case, there are other reasons, connected with the different attitudes we have to regret and remorse in individual and collective cases, for preferring a communicative to a denunciatory account here.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Civics, Policy, and Demoralization.Jonathan Jacobs - 2017 - Criminal Justice Ethics 36 (1):25-44.
    Civics can be distinguished from policy. Civics concerns basic principles and institutions of political and legal order. Policy concerns specific ways in which particular ends are pursued by the st...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Compulsory Medication, Trial Competence, and Penal Theory.Jesper Ryberg - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Capacity as Philosophy: A Review of Richard Lippke’s, The Ethics of Plea Bargaining: Richard L. Lippke: The Ethics of Plea Bargaining. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, 258pp, ISBN: 98-0-19-964146-8. [REVIEW]Sarah Armstrong - 2014 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1):265-281.
    Plea bargaining is a response to capacity overload in the criminal justice system. It both preserves and belies the right to trial, making possible its glorious display but only by denying it in most cases. While plea bargaining has been documented and analysed copiously in historical, sociological and legal terms, its ethical status as an institutional practice are hazy. Richard Lippke offers an account of plea bargaining that draws on the normative debates over responsibility, culpability and desert, in aid of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Retributivism and the (Lack of) Justification of Proportionality.Jesper Ryberg - 2021 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3):447-462.
    The principle of proportionality has gained widespread adherence in the modern retributively-dominated era of penal theory. It has often been held that, if one subscribes to a retributivist theory, then one is also committed to proportionality in punishment. In the present article, this assumption is challenged. It is shown that the inference from the fact that one offender has committed a more serious crime than another offender, to the conclusion that this offender should be punished more severely than the other, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Iniuria Migrandi: Criminalization of Immigrants and the Basic Principles of the Criminal Law. [REVIEW]Alessandro Spena - 2014 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (3):635-657.
    In this paper I am specifically concerned with a normative assessment, from the perspective of a principled criminal law theory, of norms criminalizing illegal immigration. The overarching question I will dwell on is one specifically regarding the way of using criminal law which is implied in the enactment of such kinds of norms. My thesis will essentially be that it constitutes a veritable abuse of criminal law. In two senses at least: first, in the sense that by criminalizing illegal immigration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Communication, Punishment, and Virtue.Richard Bourne - 2014 - Journal of Religious Ethics 42 (1):78-107.
    This essay suggests that while Antony Duff's model of criminal punishment as secular penance is pregnant with possibilities for theological reception and reflection, it proceeds by way of a number of separations that are brought into question by the penitential traditions of Christianity. The first three of these—between justice and mercy, censure and invitation, and state and victim, constrain the true communicative character of his account of punishment. The second set of oppositions, between sacrament and virtue, interior character and external (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Legal Punishment and the Public Identification of Offenders.Richard L. Lippke - 2018 - Res Publica 24 (2):199-216.
    In the United States, the identities of criminal offenders are matters of public record, accessible to prospective employers, the press, and ordinary citizens. In European countries, the identities of offenders are routinely kept hidden, with some exceptions. The question addressed in this discussion concerns whether the public disclosure of the identities of offenders is part and parcel of their legal punishment. My contentions are that public disclosure is not conceptually part of legal punishment, necessary to serve substantive penal aims, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct paternalism: Criminalizing self‐injurious conduct.Andrew Von Hirsch - 2008 - Criminal Justice Ethics 27 (1):25-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations