Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The task of the bow: Heraclitus' rhetorical critique of epic language.Carol Poster - 2006 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 39 (1):1-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • VI—Paradoxes as Philosophical Method and Their Zenonian Origins.Barbara M. Sattler - 2021 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 121 (2):153-181.
    In this paper I show that one of the most fruitful ways of employing paradoxes has been as a philosophical method that forces us to reconsider basic assumptions. After a brief discussion of recent understandings of the notion of paradoxes, I show that Zeno of Elea was the inventor of paradoxes in this sense, against the background of Heraclitus’ and Parmenides’ way of argumentation: in contrast to Heraclitus, Zeno’s paradoxes do not ask us to embrace a paradoxical reality; and in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heraclitus on the Question of a Common Measure.Sarah Feldman - 2023 - Rhizomata 11 (1):1-32.
    This paper offers a new reading of Heraclitus fragment B90 (Diels-Kranz). It argues that we can enrich our understanding of the fragment by reading it, not as a primitive analogy, but as a skillful simile grounded both in the poetic tradition and in the cultural context that would have conditioned its significance for Heraclitus and his audience. Read in this way, B90’s evocation of a cosmos whose common measure parallels the common measure of the polis’ marketplace is not simply a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heraclitus, Change and Objective Contradictions in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Γ.Celso Vieira - 2022 - Rhizomata 10 (2):183-214.
    In Metaphysics Γ, Aristotle argues against those who seem to accept contradictions. He distinguishes between the Sophists, who deny the principle of non-contradiction through arguments, and the Natural Philosophers, whose physical investigations lead to the acceptance of objective contradictions. Heraclitus’ name appears throughout the discussion. Usually, he is associated with the discussion against the Sophists. In this paper, I explore how the discussion with the Natural Philosophers may illuminate both the interpretation of Heraclitus by Aristotle and Heraclitus’ own worldview. To (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Phusis, Opposites and Ontological Dependence in Heraclitus.Richard Neels - 2018 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 35 (3):199-217.
    The earliest recorded philosophical use of the term "phusis" occurs in the fragments of Heraclitus (most notably at B1 and B123). Phusis, in the non-philosophical writings relevant to Heraclitus’s time (e.g. from Homer to Aeschylus and Pindar), was generally used to characterize the external physical appearance of something. Heraclitus, on the other hand, seems to have used the term in the completely opposite manner: an object’s phusis is hidden (kruptesthai) and greater (kreissōn) than the external appearance (B123 and B54). Despite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heraclitus' Bow Composition.Celso Vieira - 2013 - Classical Quarterly 63 (2):473-490.
    This article aims to throw light on a recurrent structural feature of Heraclitus' style that, it will be argued, serves as a tool to enrich interpretation of his fragments. Named after the bow image used by the philosopher in B51, the ‘bow composition’ will be presented as a narrative technique developed by Heraclitus to reveal his conception of the world. In B51 we read: οὐ ξυνιᾶσιν ὅκως διαϕερόμενον ἑωυτῶι ὁμολογέει· παλίντροπος ἁρμονίη ὅκωσπερ τόξου καὶ λύρης (‘They don't understand how what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Herakleitas: λογος kaip φυσις bylojimas.Skirmantas Jankauskas - 2019 - Problemos 95:8-21.
    [straipsnis ir santrauka lietuvių kalba; santrauka anglų kalba] Straipsnyje pateikiama savita herakleitiškojo Logo kaip mąstančio kalbėjimo interpretacija. Iš pradžių aptariamos antikinio filosofavimo bendrosios ontologinės ir gnoseologinės prielaidos. Bene svarbiausia šio filosofavimo nuostata yra laikoma mąstymo subjekto ir objekto perskyros reliatyvumas. Todėl į efesiečio aforizmus straipsnyje žiūrima kaip fenomenologines įžvalgas. Laikantis tokio požiūrio, mėginama eksplikuoti efesiečio pagrindinio aforizmo (DK22 B1) turinį. Šio aforizmo prasmė pamažu atskleidžiama pasitelkiant kitus Herakleito aforizmus. Kadangi pavieniai aforizmai ir jų grupės atveria skirtingus herakleitiškojo filosofavimo aspektus, tai (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark