Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Criteria of empirical significance: a success story.Sebastian Lutz - manuscript
    The sheer multitude of criteria of empirical significance has been taken as evidence that the pre-analytic notion being explicated is too vague to be useful. I show instead that a significant number of these criteria—by Ayer, Popper, Przełęcki, Suppes, and David Lewis, among others—not only form a coherent whole, but also connect directly to the theory of definition, the notion of empirical content as explicated by Ramsey sentences, and the theory of measurement; two criteria by Carnap and Sober are trivial, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The idea of rationality and its relationship to social science: Comments on Popper's philosophy of the social sciences.Michael Schmid - 1988 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 31 (4):451 – 469.
    Popper has proposed a ?theory of situational rationality? as a basis for the social sciences. This theory of rational action is reconstructed and its methodological and substantial implications discussed. It is shown that methodologically Popper's idea of rational action leads to a version of theoretical instrumentalism which is incompatible with his general philosophy of science, and that substantially it implies an unacceptable theory of social institutions. Instrumentalism can be avoided by a more contentful theory of human action encompassing ?non?rational? or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Theories, systemic models (SYMOs), laws and facts in the sciences.G. D. Wassermann - 1989 - Synthese 79 (3):489 - 514.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On demographic factors and neurohormonal substrates.A. B. Bubenik - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):624-625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the nature of the theory of evolution.Gerhard D. Wassermann - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (3):416-437.
    This paper supplements an earlier one (Wassermann 1978b). Its views aim to reinforce those of Lewontin and other prominent evolutionists, but differ significantly from the opinions of some philosophers of science, notably Popper (1957) and Olding (1978). A basic distinction is made between 'laws' and 'theories of mechanisms'. The 'Theory of Evolution' is not characterized by laws, but is viewed here as a hypertheory which explains classifiable evolutionary phenomena in terms of subordinate classifiable theories of 'evolution-specific mechanisms' (ESMs), each of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Criteria of Empirical Significance: Foundations, Relations, Applications.Sebastian Lutz - 2012 - Dissertation, Utrecht University
    This dissertation consists of three parts. Part I is a defense of an artificial language methodology in philosophy and a historical and systematic defense of the logical empiricists' application of an artificial language methodology to scientific theories. These defenses provide a justification for the presumptions of a host of criteria of empirical significance, which I analyze, compare, and develop in part II. On the basis of this analysis, in part III I use a variety of criteria to evaluate the scientific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Jumping on the Sociobiology bandwagon.I. Eibl-Eibesfeldt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):631-634.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How much can the ethological approach contribute to an understanding of human behavior?Hubert S. Markl - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):626-627.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wallace’s and Darwin’s natural selection theories.Santiago Ginnobili & Daniel Blanco - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):991-1017.
    This work takes a stand on whether Wallace should be regarded as co-author of the theory of natural selection alongside Darwin as he is usually considered on behalf of his alleged essential contribution to the conception of the theory. It does so from a perspective unexplored thus far: we will argue for Darwin’s priority based on a rational reconstruction of the theory of natural selection as it appears in the writings of both authors. We show that the theory does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Positive heuristics in evolutionary biology.Richard E. Michod - 1981 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (1):1-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A critique of some aspects of human ethology.Gerhard D. Wassermann - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):630-631.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On a functional-morphological approach to phylogenetic reconstruction: A critique.Ronald Sluys - 1983 - Acta Biotheoretica 32 (1):29-41.
    A method of phylogenetic reconstruction as proposed by a number of scientists of the Senckenberg Research Institute is discussed. The method is based on functional-morphological studies, the evolutionary adaptation principle of Bock and Von Wahlert (1965) and so-called model reconstruction. It is argued in this paper that direction of the adaptation process cannot be determined because of lack of knowledge about particular selective forces and that theories of model reconstruction are not open to contradiction in the sense of Popperian falsification. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Eibl-Eibesfeldt's human ethology: The problem of evidence.Ronald C. Simons - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):629-630.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Still-life photographs: The power of human ethology in the explanation of human behavior.Robert Sapolsky & Howard Eichenbaum - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):628-629.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Austro-German ethology and schizophrenia.Roger K. Pitman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):627-628.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Persistent propensities: Portrait of a familiar controversy. [REVIEW]Alfred Nordmann - 1990 - Biology and Philosophy 5 (4):379-399.
    Susan Mills and John Beatty's propensity interpretation of fitness encountered very different philosophical criticisms by Alexander Rosenberg and Kenneth Waters. These criticisms and the rejoinders to them are both predictable and important. They are predictable as raisingkinds of issues typically associated with disposition concepts (this is established through a systematic review of the problems generated by Carnap's dispositional interpretation of all scientific terms). They are important as referring the resolution of these issues to the development of evolutionary biology. This historical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Locus of causation: analysis of ethological similarities.Gordon M. Harrington - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):625-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human ethology, biological determinism, directive genes, and trees.Marc Bekoff - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):623-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark