Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Informal Logic.Leo Groarke - 1996 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Informal logic is an attempt to develop a logic that can assess and analyze the arguments that occur in natural language discourse. Discussions in the field may address instances of scientific, legal, and other technical forms of reasoning, but the overriding aim has been a comprehensive account of argument that can explain and evaluate the arguments found in discussion, debate and disagreement as they manifest themselves in daily life — in social and political commentary; in news reports and editorials in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Mind and Body, Form and Content: How not to do Petitio Principii Analysis.Louise Cummings - 2000 - Philosophical Papers 29 (2):73-105.
    Abstract Few theoretical insights have emerged from the extensive literature discussions of petitio principii argument. In particular, the pattern of petitio analysis has largely been one of movement between the two sides of a dichotomy, that of form and content. In this paper, I trace the basis of this dichotomy to a dualist conception of mind and world. I argue for the rejection of the form/content dichotomy on the ground that its dualist presuppositions generate a reductionist analysis of certain concepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The disunity of truth.Josh Dever - 2008 - In Robert Stainton & Christopher Viger (eds.), Compositionality, Context, and Semantic Values: Essays in Honor of Ernie Lepore. Springer. pp. 174-191.
    §§3-4 of the Begriffsschrift present Frege’s objections to a dominant if murky nineteenth-century semantic picture. I sketch a minimalist variant of the pre-Fregean picture which escapes Frege’s criticisms by positing a thin notion of semantic content which then interacts with a multiplicity of kinds of truth to account for phenomena such as modality. After exploring several ways in which we can understand the existence of multiple truth properties, I discuss the roles of pointwise and setwise truth properties in modal logic. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Locke‐Stewart‐Mill: Philosophy of science at Dartmouth College, 1771‐1854.David K. Nartonis - 2001 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (2):167 – 175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasonableness and Effectiveness in Argumentative Discourse: Fifty Contributions to the Development of Pragma-Dialectics.Bart Garssen, Frans Eemeren & Frans H. van Eemeren (eds.) - 2015 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    How do Dutch people let each other know that they disagree? What do they say when they want to resolve their difference of opinion by way of an argumentative discussion? In what way do they convey that they are convinced by each other’s argumentation? How do they criticize each other’s argumentative moves? Which words and expressions do they use in these endeavors? By answering these questions this short essay provides a brief inventory of the language of argumentation in Dutch.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Deep disagreements: A meta-argumentation approach.Maurice Finocchiaro & David M. Godden - unknown
    This paper examines the views of Fogelin, Woods, Johnstone, etc., concerning deep disa-greements, force-five standoffs, philosophical controversies, etc. My approach is to reconstruct their views and critiques of them as meta-arguments, and to elaborate the meta-argumentative aspects of radical disa-greements. It turns out that deep disagreements are resolvable to a greater degree than usually thought, but only by using special principles and practices, such as meta-argumentation, ad hominem argumentation, Ramsey’s principle, etc.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Did Jesus Commit a Fallacy?Aaron Ben-Zeev - 1995 - Informal Logic 17 (2).
    Jesus has been accused of committing a fallacy (of denying the antecedent) at John 8:47. Careful analysis of this text (1) reveals a hitherto unrecognized valid form of argument which can superficially look like the predicate-logic analogue of denying the antecedent; (2) shows that determining whether a published text can be fairly charged with committing a fallacy may require (but often does not get) extensive and detailed analysis; (3) acquits Jesus of the charge; and thereby (4) conflnns a claim by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Debts, Oligarchies, and Holisms: Deconstructing the Fallacy of Composition.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 2013 - Informal Logic 33 (2):143-174.
    This is a critical appreciation of Govier’s 2006 ISSA keynote address on the fallacy of composition, and of economists’ writings on this fallacy in economics. I argue that the “fallacy of composition” is a problematical concept, because it does not denote a distinctive kind of argument but rather a plurality, and does not constitute a distinctive kind of error, but rather reduces to oversimplification in arguing from micro to macro. Finally, I propose further testing of this claim based on examples (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The doctrine of distribution.Terence Parsons - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (1):59-74.
    Peter Geach describes the 'doctrine of distribution' as the view that a term is distributed if it refers to everything that it denotes, and undistributed if it refers to only some of the things that it denotes. He argues that the notion, so explained, is incoherent. He claims that the doctrine of distribution originates from a degenerate use of the notion of ?distributive supposition? in medieval supposition theory sometime in the 16th century. This paper proposes instead that the doctrine of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Miracles.Michael Levine - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Trémaux on species: A theory of allopatric speciation (and punctuated equilibrium) before Wagner.John S. Wilkins & Gareth J. Nelson - 2008 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 30 (1):179-206.
    Pierre Trémaux’s 1865 ideas on speciation have been unjustly derided following his acceptance by Marx and rejection by Engels, and almost nobody has read his ideas in a charitable light. Here we offer an interpretation based on translating the term sol as “habitat”, in order to show that Trémaux proposed a theory of allopatric speciation before Wagner and a punctuated equilibrium theory before Gould and Eldredge, and translate the relevant discussion from the French. We believe he may have influenced Darwin’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cicero's authority.Jean Goodwin - 1999 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 34 (1):38-60.
    In this paper I propose to continue the analysis of the appeal to authority begun at the last OSSA conference. I proceed by examining the well-documented use of the appeal made by the ancient Roman advocate, Cicero. The fact that Cicero expressed his opinion was expectably sufficient to give his auditors--responsible citizens all--reason to do as he desired. But why? The resolution of this puzzle points to a strong sense in which arguments can be called rhetorical , for the rational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Is Aristotle the Forefather of Informal Logic?Louis F. Groarke - 2022 - Dialogue 61 (1):139-159.
    RésuméDans cet article, je soutiens qu'Aristote utilise une approche de la logique que l'on retrouve chez les praticiens de la logique informelle d'aujourd’hui. Même si sa position est complexe, Aristote privilégie des interprétations intensionnelles plutôt qu'extensionnelles de sa logique syllogistique. Il n'utilise pas les fonctions de vérité, mais adopte une version de la sémantique qui accentue le rôle du langage naturel qui ouvre, pour ainsi dire, une fenêtre sur la réalité métaphysique. Le mouvement de la logique informelle fut, en grande (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Road to Modern Logic—An Interpretation.Jos\'E. Ferreir\'os - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (4):441-484.
    This paper aims to outline an analysis and interpretation of the process that led to First-Order Logic and its consolidation as a core system of modern logic. We begin with an historical overview of landmarks along the road to modern logic, and proceed to a philosophical discussion casting doubt on the possibility of a purely rational justification of the actual delimitation of First-Order Logic. On this basis, we advance the thesis that a certain historical tradition was essential to the emergence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Fallacy and argumentational vice.Andrew Aberdein - 2014 - In Dima Mohammed & Marcin Lewinski (eds.), Virtues of argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 22–25, 2013. OSSA.
    If good argument is virtuous, then fallacies are vicious. Yet fallacies cannot just be identified with vices, since vices are dispositional properties of agents whereas fallacies are types of argument. Rather, if the normativity of good argumentation is explicable in terms of virtues, we should expect the wrongness of fallacies to be explicable in terms of vices. This approach is defended through case studies of several fallacies, with particular emphasis on the ad hominem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Head or tail? de morgan on the bounds of traditional logic.Víctor Sánchez Valencia - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (3):123-138.
    This paper is concerned with De Morgan’s explanation of the validity of arguments that involve relational notions. It discusses De Morgan’s expansion of traditional logic aimed at accommodating those inferences, and makes the point that his endeavour is not successful in that the rules that made up his new logic are not sound. Nevertheless, the most important scholarly work on De Morgan’s logic, and contrary to that De Morgan’s mistake is not beyond repair. The rules that determine his new logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Did Jesus Commit a Fallacy?David Hitchcock - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Composition and division.John Woods & Douglas Walton - 1977 - Studia Logica 36 (4):381 - 406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Nineteenth Century British Logic on Hypotheticals, Conditionals, and Implication.Francine F. Abeles - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (1):1-14.
    Hypotheticals, conditionals, and their connecting relation, implication, dramatically changed their meanings during the nineteenth and early part of the twentieth century. Modern logicians ordinarily do not distinguish between the terms hypothetical and conditional. Yet in the late nineteenth century their meanings were quite different, their ties to the implication relation either were unclear, or the implication relation was used exclusively as a logical operator. I will trace the development of implication as an inference operator from these earlier notions into the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thomas solly (1816–1875):an unknown pioneer of the mathematization of logic in england, 1839.M. Pabteki - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2):133-169.
    (1993). Thomas solly (1816–1875):an unknown pioneer of the mathematization of logic in england, 1839. History and Philosophy of Logic: Vol. 14, No. 2, pp. 133-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Theoretical Unity of Aristotle’s Categorical Syllogistic and Sophistics.Gonzalo Llach - forthcoming - History and Philosophy of Logic:1-18.
    The hypothesis of a theoretical unity between On Sophistical Refutations and Prior Analytics presents a major challenge to scholars attempting to unify the criteria of analysis. This paper examines this problem and proposes a middle ground between the perspectives of Woods and Boger to address this crucial question: If a unitary and coherent theory of deduction exists, why does not the technical apparatus of syllogistic modes for analyzing fallacies appear in SE? This paper makes useful contributions to the discussion on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Revision and Immortality in Philosophical Argumentation: Continuing Thoughts on the Rhetorical Wedge.Mari Lee Mifsud - 2001 - Informal Logic 21 (1).
    This essay explores Johnstone's idea that "rhetoric is a wedge." In particular, it explores the place of this idea in Johnstone's philosophy of argument, the need to confront this idea with argument, and ways of confronting it with ad rem and ad hominem arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plausible Reasoning. By Nicholas Rescher. Assen/Amsterdam: Van Gorcum. 1976. Pp. 124.Douglas N. Walton - 1977 - Dialogue 16 (4):774-779.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Essay Review.Volker Peckhaus - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):115-120.
    Jarmo Pulkkinen, The threat of logical mathematism. A study on the critique of mathematical logic in Germany at the turn of the 20th century. Frankfurt a.M:Peter Lang, 1994. Scandinavian University Studies in the Humanities and Social Sciences; 7). 186 pp. 24 DM. ISBN 3-631-47409-1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Argumentation: Logic and Rhetoric. [REVIEW]S. Frogel - 2004 - Argumentation 18 (2):171-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Valid Ad Hominem Arguments in Philosophy: Johnstone's Metaphilosophical Informal Logic.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 2001 - Informal Logic 21 (1).
    This is a critical examination of Johnstone's thesis that all valid philosophical arguments are ad hominem. I clarify his notions of valid, philosophical, and ad hominem. I illustrate the thesis with his refutation ofthe claim that only ordinary language is correct. r discuss his three supporting arguments (historical, theoretical, and intermediate). And r criticize the thesis with the objections that if an ad hominem argument is valid, it is really ad rem; that it's unclear how his own theoretical argument can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • El uso de falacias en la comunicación absurda.Jesús Portillo Fernández - 2018 - Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 28 (2):443-458.
    In this paper we study the inferential analysis of the use of fallacies as a source of absurd communication. Starting from a diachronic review of perpectives, criteria and classification of fallacies, we analyze the fallacious arguments used in absurd discourses which are meant to trigger humor as well as the dislocation of the communicative sense.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locke and “ad”.Richard Davies - 2023 - Argumentation 37 (3):473-492.
    In IV, xvii, 19–22 of his Essay, Locke employs Latin labels for four kinds of argument, of which one (ad hominem) was already in circulation and one (ad judicium) has never had much currency. The present proposal seeks to locate and clarify what Locke was aiming to describe, and to contrast what he says with some subsequent uses that have been made of these labels as if they named fallacies. Though three of the four kinds of argument that Locke picks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark