Switch to: References

Citations of:

On Human Nature

Philosophical Review 88 (4):660-663 (1979)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Discourses on war.Roger Cooter - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (4):637-647.
    Members of the Ba2Zn1-xCdxTa2O9 series have been synthesized by solid state reactions at 1473 K. Powder x-ray diffraction studies show a cubic perovskite cell with a ~ 4.1 a which increases with increase in x. Electron diffraction studies show the presence of hexagonal ordered perovskite structure in addition to the cubic structure seen by x-rays, the x = 0.5 composition showing more ordered crystallites. These samples show high dielectric constants with a maximum for the x = 0.5 member. The dielectric (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When is biology destiny? Biological determinism and social responsibility.Inmaculada de Melo-Martín - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1184-1194.
    I argue here that critics of biological explanations of human nature are mistaken when they maintain that the truth of genetic determinism implies the end of critical evaluation and reform of our social institutions. Such a claim erroneously presupposes that our social values, practices, and institutions have nothing to do with what makes biological explanations troublesome. What constitutes a problem for those who are concerned with social justice is not the fact that particular behaviors might be genetically determined, but the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Taylor-ing Ethics: Implications of Charles Taylor’s Work of Retrieval on Moral Foundations Theory.Carolyn T. Dang - 2023 - Business Ethics Quarterly 33 (4):655-681.
    This article draws from Charles Taylor’s work of retrieval to advance moral foundations theory (MFT). Taylor’s contribution to MFT lies in his insistence that we retrieve the moral sources that have helped constitute, substantiate, and give meaning to individuals’ moral sensibilities. Applying Taylor’s insights to MFT, this article seeks to advance a view of moral foundations that connects them more explicitly to their underlying moral sources. Using this retrieved account of moral foundations, this article then addresses current issues within moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non-Personal Minds.Stephen R. L. Clark - 2003 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 53:185-209.
    Persons are creatures with a range of personal capacities. Most known to us are also people, though nothing in observation or biological theory demands that all and only people are persons, nor even that persons, any more than people, constitute a natural kind. My aim is to consider what non-personal minds are like. Darwin's Earthworms are sensitive, passionate and, in their degree, intelligent. They may even construct maps, embedded in the world they perceive around them, so as to be able (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How We Think about Human Nature: The Naturalizing Error.Douglas Allchin & Alexander J. Werth - 2020 - Philosophy of Science 87 (3):499-517.
    History is littered with scientifically ill-founded claims about human nature. They frequently appear in normative contexts, projecting ideology or values onto nature (what we call the naturalizing...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Foundational Paradigms of Social Sciences.Shiping Tang - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (2):211-249.
    When stripped to the bare bone, there are only 11 foundational paradigms in social sciences. These foundational paradigms are like flashlights that can be utilized to shed light on different aspects of human society, but each of them can only shed light on a limited area of human society. Different schools in social science result from different but often incomplete combinations of these foundational paradigms. To adequately understand human society and its history, we need to deploy all 11 foundational paradigms, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In the Beginning: The Role of Myth in Relating Religion, Brain Science, and Mental Well‐Being.Jaime Wright - 2018 - Zygon 53 (2):375-391.
    Building upon the insights of scholars attuned to story, narrative, and myth, this article explores the relationship between myth, science, and religion. After clarifying the interplay of the three terms—story, narrative, and myth—and the preference for the term myth, this article will argue that myth can serve as a medium through which religion, neuroscience, and mental well‐being interact. Such an exploration will cover the role of myths in religion, the neurological basis of myth, and the practices of narrative psychology and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Biologising’ Putnam: saving the realism in internal realism.Michael Vlerick - 2014 - South African Journal of Philosophy 33 (3):271-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relocating the Conflict Between Science and Religion at the Foundations of the History of Science.James C. Ungureanu - 2018 - Zygon 53 (4):1106-1130.
    Historians of science and religion usually trace the origins of the “conflict thesis,” the notion that science and religion have been in perennial “conflict” or “warfare,” to the late nineteenth century, particularly to the narratives of New York chemist John William Draper and historian Andrew Dickson White. In this essay, I argue against that convention. Their narratives should not be read as stories to debunk, but rather as primary sources reflecting themes and changes in religious thought during the late nineteenth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From Human Nature to Moral Philosophy.Mariam Thalos - 2002 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (sup1):85-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critical notice.Kim Sterelny - 1981 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (4):442 – 453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Critical notice.Kim Sterelny - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (4):538 – 555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inaugural lecture: Philosophy enough.David Spurrett - 2009 - South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (1):43-64.
    This inaugural lecture was delivered at the Howard College Campus of UKZN on 2 April 2008. In it I do three things. First I sketch some arguments in favour of a naturalist conception of philosophy. The conclusions that I’m after are that philosophy is not an autonomous enterprise, so that it had better be continuous with scientific enquiry if it is to get anywhere. A supplementary claim I defend briefly is that the natural and social sciences should be viewed as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science and Human Nature.Richard Samuels - 2012 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 70:1-28.
    There is a puzzling tension in contemporary scientific attitudes towards human nature. On the one hand, evolutionary biologists correctly maintain that the traditional essentialist conception of human nature is untenable; and moreover that this is obviously so in the light of quite general and exceedingly well-known evolutionary considerations. On the other hand, talk of human nature abounds in certain regions of the sciences, especially in linguistics, psychology and cognitive science. In this paper I articulate a conception of human nature that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Intergroup Cooperation in Common Pool Resource Dilemmas.Jathan Sadowski, Susan G. Spierre, Evan Selinger, Thomas P. Seager, Elizabeth A. Adams & Andrew Berardy - 2015 - Science and Engineering Ethics 21 (5):1197-1215.
    Fundamental problems of environmental sustainability, including climate change and fisheries management, require collective action on a scale that transcends the political and cultural boundaries of the nation-state. Rational, self-interested neoclassical economic theories of human behavior predict tragedy in the absence of third party enforcement of agreements and practical difficulties that prevent privatization. Evolutionary biology offers a theory of cooperation, but more often than not in a context of discrimination against other groups. That is, in-group boundaries are necessarily defined by those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evolutionary Ethics and the Search for Predecessors: Kant, Hume, and All the Way Back to Aristotle?Michael Ruse - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 8 (1):59.
    Hopes of applying the findings and speculations of evolutionary theorizing to the problems of ethics have yielded a program with a bad reputation. At the level of norms – substantival ethics – it has been a platform for some of the more grotesque socio-politico-economic suggestions of our times. At the level of justification – metaethics – it has opened the way to some of the more blatant fallacies in the undergraduate textbook. Recently, however, a number of people, philosophers and biologists, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Evolutionary Ethics: Healthy Prospect or Last Infirmity?Michael Ruse - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (S1):27-73.
    Evolutionary ethics, the idea that the evolutionary process contains the basis for a full and adequate understanding of human moral nature, is an old and disreputable notion. It was popularized in the 19th century by the English general man of science, Herbert Spencer, who began advocating an evolutionary approach to ethical understanding, even before Charles Darwin published hisOrigin of Speciesin 1859 (Spencer 1857, 1892). Although it was never regarded with much enthusiasm by professional philosophers, thanks to Spencer’s advocacy the evolutionary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Really taking Darwin seriously: An alternative to Michael Ruse's Darwinian metaethics. [REVIEW]William A. Rottschaefer & David Martinsen - 1990 - Biology and Philosophy 5 (2):149-173.
    Michael Ruse has proposed in his recent book Taking Darwin Seriously and elsewhere a new Darwinian ethics distinct from traditional evolutionary ethics, one that avoids the latter's inadequate accounts of the nature of morality and its failed attempts to provide a naturalistic justification of morality. Ruse argues for a sociobiologically based account of moral sentiments, and an evolutionary based casual explanation of their function, rejecting the possibility of ultimate ethical justification. We find that Ruse's proposal distorts, overextends and weakens both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Justification through biological faith: A rejoinder. [REVIEW]Robert J. Richards - 1986 - Biology and Philosophy 1 (3):337-354.
    Though I have not found enough of the latter to test out this bromide, I am sensible of the value bestowed by colleagues who have taken such exacting care in analyzing my arguments. While their incisive observation and hard objections threaten to leave an extinct theory, I hope the reader will rather judge it one strengthened by adversity. Let me initially expose the heart of my argument so as to make obvious the shocks it must endure. I ask the reader (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Critique and Investigation of the Evolutionary Ethical Behavior Explanations based on Francisco Ayala’s Theories.Haleh Abdollahi Rad & Hassan Miandari - 2020 - Philosophical Investigations 14 (32):1-20.
    Ayala (American philosopher and biologist) has presented new theories on the evolutionary ethical explanations. Due to the large scope of Ayala’s discussion on evolutionary ethics, only some of his theories will be reviewed in this paper after mentioning Ayala’s theoretical foundations about the formation of moral sense and moral norms. Following Darwin, Ayala distinguishes the moral sense and the moral norms accepted by the human community. Therefore, he believes that the biological-natural processes lead to the evolution of the human mind; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hartmann's stratified reality.Alberto Peruzzi - 2001 - Axiomathes 12 (3-4):227-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • John haught—finding consonance between religion and science.Ann M. Michaud - 2010 - Zygon 45 (4):905-920.
    John Haught has awarded the debates between religion (Christianity in particular) and science a central place in his ongoing corpus of work. Seeking to encourage and enhance the conversation, Haught both critiques current positions and offers his own perspective as a potential ground for continuing the discussion in a fruitful manner. This essay considers Haught's primary criticisms of the voices on both sides of the debate which his work connotes as polarizing or conflating the debate. It also extrudes from Haught's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A reply: The future of international morality. [REVIEW]Mary Maxwell - 1995 - Biology and Philosophy 10 (4):459-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The scientific character of Philip Hefner's “created co‐creator”.Victoria Lorrimar - 2017 - Zygon 52 (3):726-746.
    Philip Hefner's understanding of humans as “created co-creators” has played a key role in the science and religion field, particularly as scholars consider the implications of emerging technologies for the human future. Hefner articulates his “created co-creator” framework in the form of scientifically testable hypotheses supporting his core understanding of human nature, adopting the structure of Imre Lakatos's scientific research programme. This article provides a brief exposition of Hefner's model, examines his hypotheses in order to assess their scientific character, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral Motivation: Kantians versus Humeans (and Evolution).Laurence Thomas - 1988 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1):367-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Developmental decomposition and the future of human behavioral ecology.Philip Kitcher - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (1):96-117.
    I attempt to complement my earlier critiques of human sociobiology, by offering an account of how evolutionary ideas might legitimately be employed in the study of human social behavior. The main emphasis of the paper is the need to integrate studies of proximate mechanisms and their ontogenesis with functional/evolutionary research. Human psychological complexity makes it impossible to focus simply on specific types of human behavior and ask for their functional significance. For any of the kinds of behavior patterns that have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Mother/nature a skeptical look at the unique naturalness of maternal parenting.Hugh T. Wilder - 1983 - Journal of Social Philosophy 14 (2):1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mechanism, purpose and progress: Darwin and early American psychology.John D. Greenwood - 2008 - History of the Human Sciences 21 (1):103-126.
    Histories of psychology regularly celebrate the foundational role played in the development of early American psychology by Darwin's theory of evolution through natural selection, and in particular the development of functional psychology and behaviorism. In this article it is argued that although Darwin's theory did play an influential role, early American psychology did not generally reflect the hereditarian determinism of his theory of evolution by natural selection. However, early American psychologists did accept one critical implication of Darwin's theory, which is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ovid, Now and Then.Marjorie Garber - 2013 - Critical Inquiry 40 (1):133-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nature, Nurture and Why the Pendulum Still Swings.Brian Garvey - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (2):309-330.
    In both popular and technical discussion we often find the pairs of opposed terms ‘innate/acquired,’ ‘due to genes/due to environment,’ ‘nature/nurture,’ and so forth. They appear to be used as if they all captured a genuine distinction, and the same distinction at that. A related family of opposed pairs is held to describe the difference between those who attribute a certain trait to ‘nature’ and those who attribute it to ‘nurture’: ‘nativists’ versus ‘constructivists’ is one such pair. Chomsky and his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Humanistic Management: Protecting Dignity and Promoting Well-Being, by Michael Pirson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017. 310 pp. [REVIEW]Christian Felber - 2019 - Business Ethics Quarterly 29 (2):273-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mackie vs Plantinga on the warrant of theistic belief without arguments.Domingos Faria - 2016 - Scientia et Fides 4 (1):77.
    My aim in this paper is to critically assess two opposing theses about the epistemology of religious belief. The first one, developed by John Mackie, claims that belief in God can be justified or warranted only if there is a good argument for the existence of God. The second thesis, elaborated by Alvin Plantinga, holds that even if there is no such argument, belief in God can be justified or warranted. I contend that the first thesis is plausibly false, because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Crypto‐Mrtaphysic of ‘Ultimate Causes’ Remarks on an Alleged Exposé.Andreas Dorschel - 2006 - Ratio 1 (2):97-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Morality and Nature: Evolutionary Challenges to Christian Ethics.Johan De Tavernier - 2014 - Zygon 49 (1):171-189.
    Christian ethics accentuates in manifold ways the unique character of human nature. Personalists believe that the mind is never reducible to material and physical substance. The human person is presented as the supreme principle, based on arguments referring to free‐willed actions, the immateriality of both the divine spirit and the reflexive capacity, intersubjectivity and self‐consciousness. But since Darwin, evolutionary biology slowly instructs us that morality roots in dispositions that are programmed by evolution into our nature. Historically, Thomas Huxley, “Darwin's bulldog,” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations