Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Similarity and rules: distinct? exhaustive? empirically distinguishable?Ulrike Hahn & Nick Chater - 1998 - Cognition 65 (2-3):197-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Algebra Mal‐Rules and Cognitive Accounts of Error.Stephen J. Payne & Helen R. Squibb - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (3):445-481.
    We report an empirical study of elementary algebra errors, conducted in three separate schools. The errors are diagnosed using mal‐rules, as proposed by Sleeman (1984, 1,985). Our analysis uncovers the following properties of algebra mal‐rules: The frequency of mal‐rules is severely skewed, there are many infrequent mal‐rules and few frequent ones; mal‐rules are very unstable, students typically use mal‐rules very irregularly; different mal‐rules have explanatory power in different schools (many of our most powerful mal‐rules are previously unreported); mal‐rule diagnosis Is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Nature and Origin of Rational Errors in Arithmetic Thinking: Induction from Examples and Prior Knowledge.Talia Ben-Zeev - 1995 - Cognitive Science 19 (3):341-376.
    Students systematically and deliberately apply rule‐based but erroneous algorithms to solving unfamiliar arithmetic problems. These algorithms result in erroneous solutions termed rational errors. Computationally, students' erroneous algorithms can be represented by perturbations or bugs in otherwise correct arithmetic algorithms (Brown & VanLehn, 1980; Langley & Ohilson, 1984; VanLehn, 1983, 1986, 1990; Young S O'Sheo, 1981). Bugs are useful for describing how rational errors occur but bugs are not sufficient for explaining their origin. A possible explanation for this is that rational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An Attempt to Understand Students' Understanding of Basic Algebra.D. Sleeman - 1984 - Cognitive Science 8 (4):387-412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Diversity and Unity of Modularity.Bongrae Seok - 2006 - Cognitive Science 30 (2):347-380.
    Since the publication of Fodor's (1983) The Modularity of Mind, there have been quite a few discussions of cognitive modularity among cognitive scientists. Generally, in those discussions, modularity means a property of specialized cognitive processes or a domain-specific body of information. In actuality, scholars understand modularity in many different ways. Different characterizations of modularity and modules were proposed and discussed, but they created misunderstanding and confusion. In this article, I classified and analyzed different approaches to modularity and argued for the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Thinking as a production system.Marsha C. Lovett & John R. Anderson - 2005 - In K. Holyoak & B. Morrison (eds.), The Cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. pp. 401--429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Non‐LIFO Execution of Cognitive Procedures.Kurt VanLehn, William Ball & Bernadette Kowalski - 1989 - Cognitive Science 13 (3):415-465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Literature from cognitive psychology.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1982 - Artificial Intelligence 19 (3):251-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the Nature of Verbal Rules and Their Role in Problem Solving.Seth Chaiklin - 1984 - Cognitive Science 8 (2):131-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark