Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Defending Historical Autonomy: A Reply to Professor Mele.John Christman - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):281 - 289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Autonomy and Personal History.John Christman - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1):1 - 24.
    Virtually any appraisal of a person’s welfare, integrity, or moral status, as well as the moral and political theories built on such appraisals, will rely crucially on the presumption that her preferences and values are in some important sense her own. In particular, the nature and value of political freedom is intimately connected with the presupposition that actions one is left free to do flow from desires and values that are truly an expression of the ‘self-government’ of the agent. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  • Autonomy and hierarchy.Michael E. Bratman - 2003 - Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (2):156-176.
    In autonomous action the agent herself directs and governs the action. But what is it for the agent herself to direct and to govern? One theme in a series of articles by Harry G. Frankfurt is that we can make progress in answering this question by appeal to higher-order conative attitudes. Frankfurt's original version of this idea is that in acting of one's own free will, one is not acting simply because one desires so to act. Rather, it is also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Emotional ambivalence.Philip J. Koch - 1987 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (2):257-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A Phenomenological Investigation of the Experience of Ambivalence.Steve Harrist - 2006 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 37 (1):85-114.
    Ambivalence, broadly defined as feeling more than one emotion at a time, is thought to be a central aspect of human experience and to play an important role in a range of psychological processes. Ambivalence is experienced in close relationships, identity development, social and political attitudes, decision-making behavior, anxiety states, as well as in psychotherapeutic change. Eight under-graduate students participated in phenomenological interviews that were transcribed and served as the basis for the investigation. The primary purpose of this paper is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The paradox of horror.Berys Gaut - 1993 - British Journal of Aesthetics 33 (4):333-345.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Some Thoughts About Caring.Harry Frankfurt - 1998 - Ethical Perspectives 5 (1):3-14.
    In their discussions of issues concerning the nature of human action, and also in their inquiries into the structure of practical reasoning, philosophers typically draw upon a more or less standard conceptual repertoire. The most familiar item in that repertoire is the indispensable, ubiquitous, and protean notion of what people want or — synonymously, at least in the usage that I shall adopt — what they desire. I believe that the elementary repertoire in which the concept of desire is so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A coherence theory of autonomy.Laura Waddell Ekstrom - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3):599-616.
    This paper presents a conception of the self partially in terms of a particular notion of preference. It develops a coherentist account of when one's preferences are "authorized", or sanctioned as one's own, and presents a coherence theory of autonomous action. The view presented solves certain problems with hierarchical accounts of freedom, such as Harry Frankfurt's.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Taking ourselves seriously & Getting it right.Harry G. Frankfurt - 2006 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. Edited by Debra Satz.
    Harry G. Frankfurt begins his inquiry by asking, “What is it about human beings that makes it possible for us to take ourselves seriously?” Based on The Tanner Lectures in Moral Philosophy, Taking Ourselves Seriously and Getting It Right delves into this provocative and original question. The author maintains that taking ourselves seriously presupposes an inward-directed, reflexive oversight that enables us to focus our attention directly upon ourselves, and “[it] means that we are not prepared to accept ourselves just as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Standing for something.Cheshire Calhoun - 1995 - Journal of Philosophy 92 (5):235-260.
    Three pictures of integrity have gained philosophical currency. On the integrated self picture, integrity involves the integration of "parts" of oneself into a whole. On the identity picture, integrity means fidelity to projects and principles constitutive of one's core identity. On the clean hands picture, integrity means maintaining the purity of one's agency, especially in dirty hands situations. I sketch each picture and suggest two general criticisms. First, integrity is reduced to something else with which it is not equivalent--to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Ethical Theory.W. F. R. Hardie & J. Donald Monan - 1968 - Ethics 80 (1):76-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • A Case of Mixed Feelings: Ambivalence and the Logic of Emotion.Patricia Greenspan - 1980 - In A. O. Rorty (ed.), Explaining Emotions. University of California Press. pp. 223--250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations