Switch to: Citations

References in:

How Did There Come To Be Two Kinds of Coercion?

In David A. Reidy & Walter J. Riker (eds.), Coercion and the State. Springer Verlag. pp. 17-29 (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Letter from a Birmingham jail.Martin Luther King Jr - 2000 - In Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Exploring Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press USA.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Is Law Coercive?William A. Edmundson - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (1):81-111.
    That law is coercive is something we all more or less take for granted. It is an assumption so rooted in our ways of thinking that it is taken as a given of social reality, an uncontroversial datum. Because it is so regarded, it is infrequently stated, and when it is, it is stated without any hint of possible complications or qualifications. I will call this the “prereflective view,” and I want to examine it with the care it deserves.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Theoretical foundations of liberalism.Jeremy Waldron - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (147):127-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Justification and legitimacy.A. John Simmons - 1999 - Ethics 109 (4):739-771.
    In this essay I will discuss the relationship between two of the most basic ideas in political and legal philosophy: the justification of the state and state legitimacy. I plainly cannot aspire here to a complete account of these matters; but I hope to be able to say enough to motivate a way of thinking about the relation between these notions that is, I believe, superior to the approach which seems to be dominant in contemporary political philosophy. Today showing that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Authority and Coercion.Arthur Ripstein - 2004 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (1):2-35.
    I am grateful to Donald Ainslie, Lisa Austin, Michael Blake, Abraham Drassinower, David Dyzenhaus, George Fletcher, Robert Gibbs, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Sari Kisilevsky, Dennis Klimchuk, Christopher Morris, Scott Shapiro, Horacio Spector, Sergio Tenenbaum, Malcolm Thorburn, Ernest Weinrib, Karen Weisman, and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs for comments, and audiences in the UCLA Philosophy Department and Columbia Law School for their questions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Difference, Diversity, and the Limits of Toleration.Kirstie M. Mcclure - 1990 - Political Theory 18 (3):361-391.
    We have no patterns for relating across our human differences as equals.Advocating the mere tolerance of difference between women is the grossest reformism.... Differences must be not merely tolerated, but seen as a fund of necessary polarities.... Audre Lorde.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Coercion: Its nature and significance.H. J. McCloskey - 1980 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (3):335-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience.David Lyons - 1996 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (1):31-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Liberalism, Autonomy, and the Politics of Neutral Concern.Joseph Raz - 1982 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7 (1):89-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Coercive proposals [rawls and gandhi].Vinit Haksar - 1976 - Political Theory 4 (1):65-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Threats and Coercion.Martin Gunderson - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (2):247 - 259.
    There is nearly universal agreement that coercion is an evil. Even when it is necessary to avoid a greater evil or to attain some good, it is still a necessary evil. There is also nearly universal agreement that, other things being equal, one ought not to exercise coercion. Here the agreement ends. There is little agreement about just when coercion is justified. More surprisingly, there is little agreement about what coercion is. This latter controversy is more fundamental, and this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Undue Inducement: Nonsense on Stilts?Ezekiel J. Emanuel - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (5):9-13.
    1. The opinions expressed are the author's own. They do not reflect any position or policy of the National Institutes of Health, Public Health Service, Department of Health and Human Services, or any of the authors affiliated organizations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Locke on Toleration.Ingrid Creppell - 1996 - Political Theory 24 (2):200-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions.Allen Buchanan & Robert O. Keohane - 2006 - Ethics and International Affairs 20 (4):405-437.
    The authors articulate a global public standard for the normative legitimacy of global governance institutions. This standard can provide the basis for principled criticism of global governance institutions and guide reform efforts in circumstances in which people disagree deeply about the demands of global justice and the role that global governance institutions should play in meeting them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • On Noncoercive Establishment.Daniel Brudney - 2005 - Political Theory 33 (6):812-839.
    In this essay, I raise the question of whether some degree of noncoercive state support for religious conceptions (broadly understood) should be left to the majoritarian branch ofgovernment. I argue that the reason not to do so is that such state support would alienate many citizens. However to take this as a sufficient reason to constrain the majoritarian branch is to accept the thesis that not being alienated from one's polity is a significant part of the human good. Those who (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy.Michael Blake - 2001 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (3):257-296.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   247 citations  
  • Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State.William Arthur Galston - 1991 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book is a major contribution to the current theory of liberalism by an eminent political theorist. It challenges the views of such theorists as Rawls, Dworkin, and Ackerman who believe that the essence of liberalism is that it should remain neutral concerning different ways of life and individual conceptions of what is good or valuable. Professor Galston argues that the modern liberal state is committed to a distinctive conception of the human good, and to that end has developed characteristic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The Enforcement of Morals.Patrick Devlin, Patrick Baron Devlin & Baron Patrick Devlin - 1965 - London ; New York [etc.] : Oxford University Press.
    Seven essays delivered as lectures in Britain and U.S.A.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Civil Disobedience.[author unknown] - 2018
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The War on Terrorism and the End of Human Rights.David Luban - unknown
    In the immediate aftermath of September 11, President Bush stated that the perpetrators of the deed would be brought to justice. Soon afterwards, the President announced that the United States would engage in a war on terrorism. The first of these statements adopts the familiar language of criminal law and criminal justice. It treats the September 11 attacks as horrific crimes—mass murders—and the government’s mission as apprehending and punishing the surviving planners and conspirators for their roles in the crimes. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Are Coerced Acts Free?Michael J. Murray & David F. Dudrick - 1995 - American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (2):109 - 123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Special ties and natural duties.Jeremy Waldron - 1993 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1):3-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Humanitarian Intervention as a Perfect Duty. A Kantian Argument".Carla Bagnoli - 2005 - Nomos 47:117-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Unethical trials of interventions to reduce perinatal transmission of the human immunodeficiency virus in developing countries.Peter Lurie & Sidney M. Wolfe - 2012 - In Stephen Holland (ed.), Arguing About Bioethics. Routledge. pp. 479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Coercion.Robert Nozick - 1969 - In White Morgenbesser (ed.), Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel. St Martin's Press. pp. 440--72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Coercion and Moral Responsibility.Denis G. Arnold - 2001 - American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (1):53 - 67.
    In this dissertation I develop a general theory of coercion that allows one to distinguish cases of interpersonal coercion from cases of persuasion or manipulation, and cases of institutional coercion from cases of oppression. The general theory of coercion that I develop includes as one component a theory of second-order coercion. Second-order coercion takes place whenever one person intentionally impairs the formation of the second-order desires of another person, or constrains them after their formation, in a way that frustrates or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Constitution of Liberty.Friedrich Hayek - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (1):77-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   268 citations  
  • De-Facing Power.Clarissa Rile Hayward - 1998 - Dissertation, Yale University
    Political scientists tend to conceptualize power as a social phenomenon that wears a "face," that is, as an instrument powerful agents use to alter the independent or authentic action of powerless actors. This view is conceptually flawed. It relies on an unsustainable definition of freedom as a state in which action is independent or authentic. What is more, it directs attention away from a series of questions that should be central to the critical analysis of power relations. The author draws (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Keeping Friendship Unregulated.Richard Stith - 2004 - Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 18 (1):263-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation