Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Saints and heroes.J. O. Urmson - 1958 - In Abraham Irving Melden (ed.), Essays in moral philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • The Nature of Rights.Leif Wenar - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (3):223-252.
    The twentieth century saw a vigorous debate over the nature of rights. Will theorists argued that the function of rights is to allocate domains of freedom. Interest theorists portrayed rights as defenders of well-being. Each side declared its conceptual analysis to be closer to an ordinary understanding of what rights there are, and to an ordinary understand- ing of what rights do for rightholders. Neither side could win a decisive victory, and the debate ended in a standoff.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Saints and Heroes: A Plea for the Supererogatory.Patricia M. McGoldrick - 1984 - Philosophy 59 (230):523 - 528.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Making room for going beyond the call.Paul McNamara - 1996 - Mind 105 (419):415-450.
    In the latter half of this century, there have been two mostly separate threads within ethical theory, one on 'superogation', one on 'common-sense morality'. I bring these threads together by systematically reflecting on doing more than one has to do. A rich and coherent set of concepts at the core of common-sense morality is identified, along with various logical connections between these core concepts. Various issues in common-sense morality emerge naturally, as does a demonstrably productive definition of doing more than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Supererogation.David Heyd - 1982 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Actions that go 'beyond the call of duty' are a common though not commonplace part of everyday life - in heroism, self-sacrifice, mercy, volunteering, or simply in small deeds of generosity and consideration. Almost universally they enjoy a high and often unique esteem and significance, and are regarded as, somehow, peculiarly good. Yet it is not easy to explain how - for if duty exhausts the moral life there is no scope to praise supererogatory acts, and if the consequentialist is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The nature of supererogation.M. W. Jackson - 1986 - Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (4):289-296.
    The concept of supererogation is an act that it is right to do but not wrong not to do. The moral trinity of the deontic logic excludes such acts from moral theory. A moral theory that is based on duty or obligation unqualified seems inevitably to make all good acts obligations, whether construed from a teleological or deontological point of view. If supererogation is a moral fact, no moral theory can survive without acknowledging it. One way to distinguish supererogation from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Supererogation.David Heyd - 2008 - Noûs.
    Actions that go 'beyond the call of duty' are a common though not commonplace part of everyday life - in heroism, self-sacrifice, mercy, volunteering, or simply in small deeds of generosity and consideration. Almost universally they enjoy a high and often unique esteem and significance, and are regarded as, somehow, peculiarly good. Yet it is not easy to explain how - for if duty exhausts the moral life there is no scope to praise supererogatory acts, and if the consequentialist is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Supererogation and rules.Joel Feinberg - 1960 - Ethics 71 (4):276-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Saints and Heroes.Elizabeth M. Pybus - 1982 - Philosophy 57 (220):193 - 199.
    In his article ‘Saints and Heroes’, Urmson argues that traditional moral theories allow at most for a threefold classification of actions in terms of their worth, and that they are therefore unsatisfactory. Since the conclusion of his argument has led to the widespread use of the term ‘acts of supererogation’, and since I do not believe that such acts exist, I propose to argue that the actions with which he is concerned not only can, but should, be contained within the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The suberogatory.Julia Driver - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (3):286 – 295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • The Meritorious And The Mandatory.Michael Clark - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79:23-33.
    Michael Clark; II*—The Meritorious and the Mandatory, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1 June 1979, Pages 23–34, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Intrinsic preferability and the problem of supererogation.Roderick M. Chisholm & Ernest Sosa - 1966 - Synthese 16 (3-4):321 - 331.
    We first summarize and comment upon a 'calculus of intrinsic preferability' which we have presented in detail elsewhere. 1 Then we set forth 'the problem of supererogation' - a problem which, according to some, has presented difficulties for deontic logic. And, finally, we propose a moral or deontic interpretation of the calculus of intrinsic preferability which, we believe, enables us to solve the problem of supererogation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Kantian Ethics and Supererogation.Marcia Baron - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (5):237.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Supererogation and Intentions of the Agent.Alfred Archer - 2013 - Philosophia 41 (2):447-462.
    It has been claimed, by David Heyd, that in order for an act to count as supererogatory the agent performing the act must possess altruistic intentions (1982 p.115). This requirement, Heyd claims, allows us to make sense of the meritorious nature of acts of supererogation. In this paper I will investigate whether there is good reason to accept that this requirement is a necessary condition of supererogation. I will argue that such a reason can be found in cases where two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Kantian ethics and supererogation.Marcia Baron - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (5):237-262.
    ...believe that his theory asks too much, demanding total devotion to morality and treating everything worth doing (and perhaps more) as a duty. But, despite their differences, the two sets of...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Common decency.Cheshire Calhoun - 2004 - In Setting the Moral Compass: Essays by Women Philosophers. Oxford University Press. pp. 128--142.
    I suggest that the normative expectations connected with common decency do not derive from a conception of what we owe each other. Instead, they derive from a constructed concept of what can be expected of a minimally well formed moral agent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The exaptive excellence of spandrels as a term and prototype.Stephen Jay Gould - unknown
    In 1979, Lewontin and I borrowed the archi- tectural term “spandrel” (using the pendentives of San Marco in Venice as an example) to designate the class of forms and spaces that arise as necessary byproducts of another decision in design, and not as adaptations for direct utility in them- selves. This proposal has generated a large literature featur- ing two critiques: (i) the terminological claim that the span- drels of San Marco are not true spandrels at all and (ii) the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Does Consequentialism Demand too Much? Recent Work on the Limits of Obligation.Shelly Kagan - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (3):239-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme.S. J. Gould & R. C. Lewontin - 1979 - In E. Sober (ed.), Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology. The Mit Press. Bradford Books. pp. 73-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   639 citations  
  • The Ethics of Requirement.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1964 - American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (2):147 - 153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Permissions and Supererogation.Joseph Raz - 1975 - American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (2):161 - 168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations