Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Speaker's reference and semantic reference.Saul A. Kripke - 1977 - In Peter A. French, Theodore Edward Uehling & Howard K. Wettstein (eds.), Studies in the philosophy of language. Morris: University of Minnesota, Morris. pp. 255-296.
    am going to discuss some issues inspired by a well-known paper ofKeith Donnellan, "Reference and Definite Descriptions,”2 but the interest—to me—of the contrast mentioned in my title goes beyond Donnellan's paper: I think it is of considerable constructive as well as critical importance to the philosophy oflanguage. These applications, however, and even everything I might want to say relative to Donnellan’s paper, cannot be discussed in full here because of problems of length. Moreover, although I have a considerable interest in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   338 citations  
  • The case for referential descriptions.Michael Devitt - 2004 - In Marga Reimer & Anne Bezuidenhout (eds.), Descriptions and beyond. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 234--260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • The principle of parsimony.Elliott Sober - 1981 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (2):145-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • (1 other version)Donnellan's distinction/Kripke's test.Marga Reimer - 1998 - Analysis 58 (2):89–100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Paul Grice and the philosophy of language.Stephen Neale - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (5):509 - 559.
    The work of the late Paul Grice (1913–1988) exerts a powerful influence on the way philosophers, linguists, and cognitive scientists think about meaning and communication. With respect to a particular sentence φ and an “utterer” U, Grice stressed the philosophical importance of separating (i) what φ means, (ii) what U said on a given occasion by uttering φ, and (iii) what U meant by uttering φ on that occasion. Second, he provided systematic attempts to say precisely what meaning is by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • (1 other version)Conversational Impliciture.Kent Bach - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (2):124-162.
    Confusion in terms inspires confusion in concepts. When a relevant distinction is not clearly marked or not marked at all, it is apt to be blurred or even missed altogether in our thinking. This is true in any area of inquiry, pragmatics in particular. No one disputes that there are various ways in which what is communicated in an utterance can go beyond sentence meaning. The problem is to catalog the ways. It is generally recognized that linguistic meaning underdetermines speaker (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   359 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference.Saul A. Kripke - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):255-276.
    am going to discuss some issues inspired by a well-known paper ofKeith Donnellan, "Reference and Definite Descriptions,”2 but the interest—to me—of the contrast mentioned in my title goes beyond Donnellan's paper: I think it is of considerable constructive as well as critical importance to the philosophy oflanguage. These applications, however, and even everything I might want to say relative to Donnellan’s paper, cannot be discussed in full here because of problems of length. Moreover, although I have a considerable interest in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   407 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Speaker’s reference and semantic reference.Saul Kripke - 2013 - In Maite Ezcurdia & Robert J. Stainton (eds.), The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy. Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press. pp. 60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Relevance.D. Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 1986 - Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 2.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   779 citations  
  • (1 other version)The encyclopedia of philosophy. [REVIEW]Mary Hesse - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (3):263-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Mindreading, communication and the learning of names for things.Paul Bloom - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1-2):37–54.
    There are two facts about word learning that everyone accepts. The first is that words really do have to be learned. There is controversy over how much conceptual structure and linguistic knowledge is innate, but nobody thinks that this is the case for the specific mappings between sounds (or signs) and meanings. This is because these mappings vary arbitrarily from culture to culture. No matter how intelligent a British baby is, for instance, she still has to learn, by attending to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mindreading and verbal communication.Anna Papafragou - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1-2):55–67.
    The idea that verbal communication involves a species of mindreading is not new. Among linguists and philosophers, largely as a result of Grice’s (1957, 1967) influence, it has long been recognized that the act of communicating involves on the part of the communicator and the addressee mutual metarepresentations of each others’ mental states. In psychology, the coordination of common ground and attention in conversation has been pursued in a variety of studies (e.g. Clark and Marshall, 1981; Bruner, 1983).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Pragmatics.S. C. Levinson - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 49 (3):531-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   532 citations  
  • Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts.Warren Ingber, Kent Bach & Robert M. Harnish - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (1):134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   262 citations  
  • Pragmatics, Implicature, Presuposition and Lógical Form.Gerald Gazdar - 1979 - Critica 12 (35):113-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   236 citations  
  • Ockham’s razor.J. J. C. Smart - 1984 - In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Principles of philosophical reasoning. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld. pp. 118--28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Studies in the Way of Words.D. E. Over - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (160):393-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   431 citations  
  • When children are more logical than adults: Experimental investigations of scalar implicature.Ira A. Noveck - 2001 - Cognition 78 (2):165-188.
    A conversational implicature is an inference that consists in attributing to a speaker an implicit meaning that goes beyond the explicit linguistic meaning of an utterance. This paper experimentallyinvestigates scalar implicature, a paradigmatic case of implicature in which a speaker's use of a term like Some indicates that the speaker had reasons not to use a more informative one from the samescale, e.g. All; thus, Some implicates Not all. Pragmatic theorists like Grice would predict that a pragmatic interpretation is determined (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Semantic Analysis.Virgil C. Aldrich - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (2):243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The acquisition of homonymy.A. Peters - 1980 - Cognition 8 (2):187-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Implicature, Explicature, and Truth-Theoretic Semantics.Robyn Carston - 1988 - In Ruth M. Kempson (ed.), Mental Representations: The Interface between Language and Reality. Cambridge University Press. pp. 155–181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Descriptions.D. E. Over - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (172):392-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought.Jennifer M. Saul - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):134-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   193 citations  
  • Thought and Reference.Bernard W. Kobes - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • A Natural History of Negation.Jon Barwise & Laurence R. Horn - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):1103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   283 citations  
  • Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. [REVIEW]Anne Bezuidenhout - 2005 - Mind 114 (455):722-728.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations