Switch to: Citations

References in:

The Ontology of Aristotle's Final Cause

Apeiron 35 (2):153-179 (2002)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Functions.Larry Wright - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (2):139-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   550 citations  
  • The Search for Ontological Emergence.Michael Silberstein & John McGeever - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (195):201-214.
    We survey and clarify some recent appearances of the term ‘emergence’. We distinguish epistemological emergence, which is merely a limitation of descriptive apparatus, from ontological emergence, which should involve causal features of a whole system not reducible to the properties of its parts, thus implying the failure of part/whole reductionism and of mereological supervenience for that system. Are there actually any plausible cases of the latter among the numerous and various mentions of ‘emergence’ in the recent literature? Quantum mechanics seems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Teleology of Nature in Aristotle.Joseph Owens - 1968 - The Monist 52 (2):159-173.
    I. An approach to the question of teleology in nature for Aristotle requires first of all a sufficiently clear understanding of the terms involved. In regard to the notion of teleology itself, there can hardly be any pertinent difficulty. The term is a modern one, and is quite definitely fixed in meaning by contemporary use. It seems to have been coined in eighteenth-century philosophical Latin to denote the study of final causes in nature. It became readily accepted in modern philosophical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Teleology and Material/Efficient Causes in Aristotle.Frank A. Lewis - 1988 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69 (1):54-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Aristotle's De Motu Animalium by Martha Craven Nussbaum. [REVIEW]Allan Gotthelf - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (6):365-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Functional analysis.Robert E. Cummins - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (November):741-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   844 citations  
  • IV.—Mechanical Explanation and Its Alternatives.C. D. Broad - 1919 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 19 (1):86-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Where's the good in teleology?Mark Bedau - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (4):781-806.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Goal-Directed Systems and the Good.Mark Bedau - 1992 - The Monist 75 (1):34-51.
    We can readily identify goal-directed systems and distinguish them from non-goal-directed systems. A woodpecker hunting for grubs is the first, a pendulum returning to rest is the second. But what is it to be a goal-directed system? Perhaps the dominant answer to this question, inspired by systems theories such as cybernetics, is that goal-directed systems are distinguished by their tendency to seek, aim at, or maintain some more-or-less easily identifiable goal. Cybernetics and the like would hold that physical systems subject (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Teleology and Natural Necessity in Aristotle.Michael Bradie & Fred D. Miller - 1984 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 1 (2):133 - 146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations