Switch to: Citations

References in:

Subsequent Consent and Blameworthiness

HEC Forum 32 (3):239-251 (2020)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Bioethics: principles, issues, and cases.Lewis Vaughn - 2010 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Moral reasoning in bioethics -- Bioethics and moral theories -- Paternalism and patient autonomy -- Truth-telling and confidentiality -- Informed consent -- Human research -- Abortion -- Reproductive technology -- Genetic choices -- Euthanasia and physician assisted suicide -- Dividing up health care resources.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A defense of subsequent consent.Eric Chwang - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (1):117-131.
    Subsequent consent can be morally efficacious. First, it licenses nostalgia and dismissiveness no more than its prior cousin does. Second, it's coherent because linked to the mental state of not minding. Third, it's just as vulnerable to bilking as prior consent is, as is clear once we distinguish between basing moral assessments on expectations versus on actual outcomes. Fourth, mind control is illegitimate because it short circuits the subject's will, not because its consent is subsequent. Finally, our intuitions about rape (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Principles of biomedical ethics.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1979 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by James F. Childress.
    Over the course of its first seven editions, Principles of Biomedical Ethics has proved to be, globally, the most widely used, authored work in biomedical ethics. It is unique in being a book in bioethics used in numerous disciplines for purposes of instruction in bioethics. Its framework of moral principles is authoritative for many professional associations and biomedical institutions-for instruction in both clinical ethics and research ethics. It has been widely used in several disciplines for purposes of teaching in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1940 citations  
  • Decision-making capacity.Louis C. Charland - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    In many Western jurisdictions, the law presumes that adult persons, and sometimes children that meet certain criteria, are capable of making their own health care decisions; for example, consenting to a particular medical treatment, or consenting to participate in a research trial. But what exactly does it mean to say that a subject has or lacks the requisite capacity to decide? This last question has to do with what is commonly called “decisional capacity,” a central concept in health care law (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Precedent autonomy and subsequent consent.John K. Davis - 2004 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (3):267-291.
    Honoring a living will typically involves treating an incompetent patient in accord with preferences she once had, but whose objects she can no longer understand. How do we respect her precedent autonomy by giving her what she used to want? There is a similar problem with subsequent consent: How can we justify interfering with someone''s autonomy on the grounds that she will later consent to the interference, if she refuses now?Both problems arise on the assumption that, to respect someone''s autonomy, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Valid consent.Emma C. Bullock - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. New York, NY: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The normative force of consent.Heidi Hurd: - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. New York, NY: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Virtue Ethics.Rosalind Hursthouse & Glen Pettigrove - 2022 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Virtue ethics is currently one of three major approaches in normative ethics. It may, initially, be identified as the one that emphasizes the virtues, or moral character, in contrast to the approach that emphasizes duties or rules (deontology) or that emphasizes the consequences of actions (consequentialism). Suppose it is obvious that someone in need should be helped. A utilitarian will point to the fact that the consequences of doing so will maximize well-being, a deontologist to the fact that, in doing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  • Harm to Self.Joel Feinberg & Donald Vandeveer - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):550-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Clinical ethics: a practical approach to ethical decisions in clinical medicine.Albert R. Jonsen, Mark Siegler & William J. Winslade - 2022 - New York: McGraw Hill. Edited by Mark Siegler & William J. Winslade.
    This book is about the ethical issues that clinicians encounter as they care for patients and is written to assist those who serve on hospital ethics committees as they deliberate about appropriate action in difficult ethical cases.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Uneasy Virtue.Julia Driver - 2001 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The predominant view of moral virtue can be traced back to Aristotle. He believed that moral virtue must involve intellectual excellence. To have moral virtue one must have practical wisdom - the ability to deliberate well and to see what is morally relevant in a given context. Julia Driver challenges this classical theory of virtue, arguing that it fails to take into account virtues which do seem to involve ignorance or epistemic defect. Some 'virtues of ignorance' are counterexamples to accounts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Harm to Self.Joel Feinberg - 1986 - Oxford University Press USA.
    This is the third volume of Joel Feinberg's highly regarded The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, a four-volume series in which Feinberg skillfully addresses a complex question: What kinds of conduct may the state make criminal without infringing on the moral autonomy of individual citizens? In Harm to Self, Feinberg offers insightful commentary into various notions attached to self-inflicted harm, covering such topics as legal paternalism, personal sovereignty and its boundaries, voluntariness and assumptions of risk, consent and its counterfeits, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist 56 (1):64-84.
    I take as my starting point the “one very simple principle” proclaimed by Mill in On Liberty … “That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Informed consent in texas: Theory and practice.Mark J. Cherry & H. Tristram Engelhardt - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (2):237 – 252.
    The legal basis of informed consent in Texas may on first examination suggest an unqualified affirmation of persons as the source of authority over themselves. This view of individuals in the practice of informed consent tends to present persons outside of any social context in general and outside of their families in particular. The actual functioning of law and medical practice in Texas, however, is far more complex. This study begins with a brief overview of the roots of Texas law (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Informed consent.Nir Eyal - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. New York, NY: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Principles of Biomedical Ethics.Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Tom L. Beauchamp & James F. Childress - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (4):37.
    Book reviewed in this article: Principles of Biomedical Ethics. By Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2231 citations  
  • Paternalism.Tziporah Kasachkoff - 1994 - Social Theory and Practice 20 (1):1-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Ontology of Consent.Larry Alexander - 2014 - Analytic Philosophy 55 (1):102-113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Justifying Paternalism.Rosemary Carter - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (March):133-145.
    1. IntroductionA paternalistic act is one in which the protection or promotion of a subject's welfare is the primary reason for attempted or successful coercive interference with an action or state of that person. My aim in this paper is to determine the conditions under which such acts are Justified. The route I take is through the concept of consent, with actual consent providing the foundation for a rather complex condition which I claim is necessary and sufficient for the Justification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Consent and wronging a person.Peter Schaber - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. New York, NY: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paternalism and Subsequent Consent.Donald Van De Veer - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):631-642.
    Some philosophers believe that appeals to promoting or maximizing good consequences are a suspect way of attempting to justify coercive interference with another person's actions. Suppose that is true. If there is a presumption that individuals have a right not to be coercively interfered with, then, foregoing utilitarian type appeals, it would seem that the only way to justify coercive interference of a paternalistic sort would be to show that under certain conditions the presumption fails.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Non-Consensual Treatment Is (Nearly Always) Morally Impermissible.Mark J. Cherry - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):789-798.
    Commentators routinely urge that it is morally permissible forcibly to treat psychiatric patients (1) to preserve the patient's best interests and (2) to restore the patient's autonomy. Such arguments specify duties of beneficence toward others, while appreciating personal autonomy as a positive value to be weighted against other factors. Varying by jurisdiction, legal statutes usually require, in addition, at least (3) that there exists the threat of harm to self or others. In this paper, I argue against embracing the first (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Clinical Ethics: A Practical Approach to Ethical Decisions in Clinical Medicine.Henry Aranow, Albert R. Jonsen, Mark Siegler & William J. Winslade - 1983 - Hastings Center Report 13 (1):32.
    Book reviewed in this article: Clinical Ethics: A Practical Approach to Ethical Decisions in Clinical Medicine. By Albert R. Jonsen, Mark Siegler, and William J. Winslade.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Paternalism and Consent in Education, or One Day You’ll be Grateful.Peter Gardner - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 17 (1):57-72.
    Peter Gardner; Paternalism and Consent in Education, or One Day You’ll be Grateful, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 17, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Resolving ethical dilemmas: a guide for clinicians.Bernard Lo - 1994 - Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins.
    Highlights of this edition include: / Important new material addressing federal privacy regulations, disclosure of medical errors, limits on residents'...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Consent as a normative power.Felix Koch - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. New York, NY: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consent as a normative power.Felix Koch - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 32-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Non-Consensual Treatment is (Nearly Always) Morally Impermissible.Mark J. Cherry - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):789-798.
    The goal of my comments regarding the case study of Eve Hyde — presented in the introduction of this symposium — is not first and foremost to resolve the conflict between individual autonomy and medical paternalism regarding non-consensual psychiatric treatment. Instead, the goal is to step back far enough from what is generally accepted as the morally appropriate basis for non-consensual psychiatric treatment, including involuntary hospitalization and medication, and to ask very basic questions about when patients may permissibly be treated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Uneasy Virtue.Julia Driver - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (1):238-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Uneasy Virtue.Julia Driver - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (211):303-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Paternalism.John Kleinig - 1985 - Law and Philosophy 4 (1):115-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Paternalism and Subsequent Consent.Donald Van De Veer - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):631 - 642.
    Some philosophers believe that appeals to promoting or maximizing good consequences are a suspect way of attempting to justify coercive interference with another person's actions. Suppose that is true. If there is a presumption that individuals have a right not to be coercively interfered with, then, foregoing utilitarian type appeals, it would seem that the only way to justify coercive interference of a paternalistic sort would be to show that under certain conditions the presumption fails.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Paternalism.Tziporah Kasachkoff - 1994 - Social Theory and Practice 20 (1):1-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Paternalism and consent in education, or one day you 'll be grateful'.Peter Gardner - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 17 (1):57–72.
    Peter Gardner; Paternalism and Consent in Education, or One Day You’ll be Grateful, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 17, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation