Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. What Are Scientific Revolutions?Thomas S. Kuhn - 1981 - Center for Cognitive Science, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
    Thomas S. Kuhn's classic book is now available with a new index.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4757 citations  
  • The four-color problem and its philosophical significance.Thomas Tymoczko - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (2):57-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Reason, Tradition, and the Progressiveness of Science.M. D. King - 1971 - History and Theory 10 (1):3-32.
    Most sociologists of science have accepted R. K. Merton's view that there is no intrinsic connection between the ideas scientists hold and the way they behave. Merton based his approach on an extended analogy between science and economics. He assumed a division between the scientific "product" governed by an inflexible a-social logic and the processes of scientiftc "production" propelled by "non-logical" social behavior. Kuhn rejects this "divorce of convenience" and argues that "local" traditions which resist rationalization characterize both the theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The four-color theorem and mathematical proof.Michael Detlefsen & Mark Luker - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (12):803-820.
    I criticize a recent paper by Thomas Tymoczko in which he attributes fundamental philosophical significance and novelty to the lately-published computer-assisted proof of the four color theorem (4CT). Using reasoning precisely analogous to that employed by Tymoczko, I argue that much of traditional mathematical proof must be seen as resting on what Tymoczko must take as being "empirical" evidence. The new proof of the 4CT, with its use of what Tymoczko calls "empirical" evidence is therefore not so novel as he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Linearity and Reflexivity in the Growth of Mathematical Knowledge.Leo Corry - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (2):409-440.
    The ArgumentRecent studies in the philosophy of mathematics have increasingly stressed the social and historical dimensions of mathematical practice. Although this new emphasis has fathered interesting new perspectives, it has also blurred the distinction between mathematics and other scientific fields. This distinction can be clarified by examining the special interaction of thebodyandimagesof mathematics.Mathematics has an objective, ever-expanding hard core, the growth of which is conditioned by socially and historically determined images of mathematics. Mathematics also has reflexive capacities unlike those of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Nicolas Bourbaki and the concept of mathematical structure.Leo Corry - 1992 - Synthese 92 (3):315 - 348.
    In the present article two possible meanings of the term mathematical structure are discussed: a formal and a nonformal one. It is claimed that contemporary mathematics is structural only in the nonformal sense of the term. Bourbaki's definition of structure is presented as one among several attempts to elucidate the meaning of that nonformal idea by developing a formal theory which allegedly accounts for it. It is shown that Bourbaki's concept of structure was, from a mathematical point of view, a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Eighteenth-Century Origins of the Concept of Scientific Revolution.I. Bernard Cohen - 1976 - Journal of the History of Ideas 37 (2):257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations