Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. That many of us should not parent.Lisa Cassidy - 2001 - Hypatia 21 (4):40-57.
    : In liberal societies (where birth control is generally accepted and available), many people decide whether or not they wish to become parents. One key question in making this decision is, What kind of parent will I be? Parenting competence can be ranked from excellent to competent to poor. Cassidy argues that those who can foresee being poor parents, or even merely competent ones, should opt not to parent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • That Many of Us Should Not Parent.Lisa Cassidy - 2006 - Hypatia 21 (4):40-57.
    In liberal societies, many people decide whether or not they wish to become parents. One key question in making this decision is, What kind of parent will I be? Parenting competence can be ranked from excellent to competent to poor. Cassidy argues that those who can foresee being poor parents, or even merely competent ones, should opt not to parent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Paternal-Fetal Harm and Men’s Moral Duty to Use Contraception: Applying the Principles of Nonmaleficence and Beneficence to Men’s Reproductive Responsibility.Lisa Campo-Engelstein - 2014 - Medicine Studies 4 (1):1-13.
    Discussions of reproductive responsibility generally draw heavily upon the principles of nonmaleficence and beneficence. However, these principles are typically only applied to women due to the incorrect belief that only women can cause fetal harm. The cultural perception that women are likely to cause fetal and child harm is reflected in numerous social norms, policies, and laws. Conversely, there is little public discussion of men and fetal and child harm, which implies that men do not (or cannot) cause such harm. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fatherhood and child support: Do men have a right to choose?Elizabeth Brake - 2005 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (1):55–73.
    My primary aim is to call into question an influential notion of paternal responsibility, namely, that fathers owe support to their children due to their causal responsibility for their existence. I argue that men who impregnate women unintentionally, and despite having taken preventative measures, do not owe child support to their children as a matter of justice; their children have no right against them to support. I argue for this on the basis of plausible principles of responsibility which have been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Reproductive Responsibility and Long‐Acting Contraceptives.John D. Arras - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (1):27-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Overconsumption and procreation: Are they morally equivalent?Thomas Young - 2001 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (2):183–192.
    I argue it is inconsistent to believe that overconsumption is wrong or bad yet believe that having children is morally permissible, insofar as they produce comparable environmental impacts, are voluntary choices, and arise from similar desires. This presents a dilemma for "mainstream environmentalists": they do not want to abandon either of those fundamental beliefs, yet must give up one of them. I present an analogical argument supporting that conclusion. After examining four attempts to undermine the analogy, I conclude that none (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Contraceptives in the Third World.Donald Warwick - 1975 - Hastings Center Report 5 (4):9-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm.Seana Shiffrin - 1999 - Legal Theory 5 (2):117-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • NorPlant and Irresponsible Reproduction.John A. Robertson - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (1):23-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Voluntary Sterilization for Childfree Women.Cristina Richie - 2013 - Hastings Center Report 43 (6):36-44.
    Approximately 47 percent of women ages fifteen to forty‐four are currently without children, and slightly more than 20 percent of white women in America will never bear children, the highest percentage in modern history. Many fertile women who are childless are voluntarily so. Although any competent person twenty‐one years or older is legally eligible for voluntary sterilization, many doctors refuse to sterilize childfree women. This essay explores various reasons a woman would want to continue in her childfree lifestyle, evaluates the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The ethics of reproductive control.Claudia Mills - 1999 - Philosophical Forum 30 (1):43–57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Bioethics' Gender.Hilde Lindemann - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (2):W15-W19.
    I argue that the field of bioethics is gendered feminine, but that the methods it uses to resist this gender identity pose real harm to actual women. Starting with an explanation of what I take ?gender? to be, I enumerate four drawbacks to being gendered feminine. I then argue that bioethics suffers from three of the same four drawbacks. I show how the field escapes the fourth disadvantage by adopting a masculine persona that inflicts damage on women, and conclude by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can we harm and benefit in creating?Elizabeth Harman - 2004 - Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1):89–113.
    The non-identity problem concerns actions that affect who exists in the future. If such an action is performed, certain people will exist in the future who would not otherwise have existed: they are not identical to any of the people who would have existed if the action had not been performed. Some of these actions seem to be wrong, and they seem to be wrong in virtue of harming the very future individuals whose existence is dependent on their having been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Beneficence and procreation.Molly Gardner - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (2):321-336.
    Consider a duty of beneficence towards a particular individual, S, and call a reason that is grounded in that duty a “beneficence reason towards S.” Call a person who will be brought into existence by an act of procreation the “resultant person.” Is there ever a beneficence reason towards the resultant person for an agent to procreate? In this paper, I argue for such a reason by appealing to two main premises. First, we owe a pro tanto duty of beneficence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Place of Parenting within a Liberal Theory of Justice.Daniel Engster - 2010 - Social Theory and Practice 36 (2):233-262.
    Parenting has an ambiguous place within the liberal tradition. On the one hand, liberal theorists have traditionally portrayed it as a private activity. On the other hand, they have also acknowledged the need for some public regulation of parenting in order to protect children’s interests. Some theorists have suggested that this ambiguity within liberalism can be best resolved by implementing parental licensing plans that would limit childrearing opportunities strictly to individuals who could prove their psychological, moral, and financial competency to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Long‐Term Contraceptives in the Criminal Justice System.Rebecca Dresser - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (1):15-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reproducing Persons: Issues in Feminist Bioethics.Laura Martha Purdy - 1996 - Cornell University Press.
    Controversies about abortion and women's reproductive technologies often seem to reflect personal experience, religious commitment, or emotional response. Laura M. Purdy believes, however, that coherent ethical principles are implicit in these controversies and that feminist bioethics can help clarify the conflicts of interest which often figure in human reproduction. As she defines the underlying issues, Purdy emphasizes the importance of taking women's interests fully into account. Reproducing Persons first explores the rights and duties connected with conception and pregnancy. Purdy asks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Abortion, Forced Labor, and War.Laura Purdy - 1996 - In Reproducing Persons: Issues in Feminist Bioethics. Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Asymmetries in the morality of causing people to exist.Jeff McMahan - 2009 - In David Wasserman & Melinda Roberts (eds.), Harming Future Persons. Springer. pp. 49--68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Why It Is Better Never to Come into Existence.David Benatar - 1997 - American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (3):345 - 355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations