Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Scientific research is a moral duty.J. Harris - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (4):242-248.
    Biomedical research is so important that there is a positive moral obligation to pursue it and to participate in itScience is under attack. In Europe, America, and Australasia in particular, scientists are objects of suspicion and are on the defensive.i“Frankenstein science”5–8 is a phrase never far from the lips of those who take exception to some aspect of science or indeed some supposed abuse by scientists. We should not, however, forget the powerful obligation there is to undertake, support, and participate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Hooked: Ethics, the Medical Profession, and the Pharmaceutical Industry.Howard Brody - 2007 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    This book explores the controversial relationship between physicians and the pharmaceutical industry, identifies the ethical tensions and controversies, and proposes numerous reforms both for medicine's own professional integrity and for effective public regulation of the industry.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Rethinking Research Ethics.Rosamond Rhodes - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (10):19-36.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upon concentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Rethinking research ethics.Rosamond Rhodes - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):7 – 28.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upoconcentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Better than Well: American Medicine Meets the American Dream.Carl Elliot - 2008 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 1 (1):185-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   152 citations  
  • Neuroethics: A philosophical challenge.Kathinka Evers - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (2):31 – 33.
    Illes and Racine (2005) give a detailed and useful description of how developments in neuroscience and related technologies have brought about numerous ethical, social, and legal challenges. These...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Participation in biomedical research is an imperfect moral duty: a response to John Harris.S. Shapshay & K. D. Pimple - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (7):414-417.
    In his paper “Scientific research is a moral duty”, John Harris argues that individuals have a moral duty to participate in biomedical research by volunteering as research subjects. He supports his claim with reference to what he calls the principle of beneficence as embodied in the “rule of rescue” , and the principle of fairness embodied in the prohibition on “free riding” . His view that biomedical research is an important social good is agreed upon, but it is argued that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Is There a Duty to Serve as a Subject in Biomedical Research?Arthur L. Caplan - 1984 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 6 (5):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Compensating Injured Research Subjects: I. The Moral Argument.James F. Childress - 1976 - Hastings Center Report 6 (6):21-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • John Harris' argument for a duty to research.Iain Brassington - 2007 - Bioethics 21 (3):160–168.
    ABSTRACTJohn Harris suggests that participation in or support for research, particularly medical research, is a moral duty. One kind of defence of this position rests on an appeal to the past, and produces two arguments. The first of these arguments is that it is unfair to accept the benefits of research without contributing something back in the form of support for, or participation in, research. A second argument is that we have a social duty to maintain those practices and institutions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Making Research a Requirement of Treatment: Why We Should Sometimes Let Doctors Pressure Patients to Participate in Research.David Orentlicher - 2005 - Hastings Center Report 35 (5):20.
    When a patient could be offered one of multiple established treatments, doctors should be able to offer treatment only if the patient agrees to participate in research aimed at determining which of the treatments is most effective. Making treatment conditional on research participation will help researchers complete badly needed studies.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Should patients be allowed to veto their participation in clinical research?H. M. Evans - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (2):198-203.
    Patients participating in the shared benefits of publicly funded health care enjoy the benefits of treatments tested on previous patients. Future patients similarly depend on treatments tested on present patients. Since properly designed research assumes that the treatments being studied are—so far as is known at the outset—equivalent in therapeutic value, no one is clinically disadvantaged merely by taking part in research, provided the research involves administering active treatments to all participants. This paper argues that, because no other practical or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Research-Related Injury: Problems and Solutions.Larry D. Scott - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (3):419-428.
    The highly publicized deaths of research participants Ellen Roche and Jesse Gelsinger are stark reminders that risk is inherent in medical research and while untoward outcomes are infrequent when compared to individual and societal benefits, injury and even death will happen. Who is responsible for the welfare of research subjects and what are they owed? Why were they put at risk to begin with? Are obligations, if any, to research subjects dependent on the type of study in which they participate, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Additional thoughts on rethinking research ethics.Richard R. Sharp & Mark Yarborough - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):40 – 42.
    Like many trained in philosophy, we greatly value the work of those scholars with the courage to espouse contrarian views, particularly when the ideas in dispute lie at the very heart of entrenched...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Free-riding and research ethics.Fritz Allhoff - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):50 – 51.
    In "Rethinking Research Ethics," Rosamond Rhodes argues that everyone has a responsibility to participate in research ethics programs (Rhodes 2005). After discussing the moral underpinnings upon which such a claim might rest, this article brings up two concerns in response to Rhodes' claim. The first worry is pragmatic: Rhodes argues that the focus in research ethics should be on the hypothetical consent of idealized moral agents, an approach that is constrained by practical considerations. The second objection is that, in most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Universal compulsory service in medical research.C. D. Herrera - 2003 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24 (3):215-231.
    Despite the prominence of healthcare-relatedconcerns in public debate, the ground remainsinfertile for the idea of conscripting citizensinto medical research. Reluctance to entertainthe thought of a system where nearly everyonecould be selected for service might reflectuncertainty about what the project wouldinvolve. There might also be a fear that themore crucial issue is how to protect researchsubjects within current, voluntary systems. Nodoubt reluctance to explore a system ofuniversal service results from the common hopethat each of us might avoid research in anycapacity besides (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Research participation: Are we subject to a duty?Robert Wachbroit & David Wasserman - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):48 – 49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Compensation for research injuries.Hazel Beh - 2004 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 27 (3):11-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Stopping trials early for commercial reasons: the risk-benefit relationship as a moral compass.A. S. Iltis - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (7):410-414.
    Decisions by industry sponsors to end clinical trials early for commercial reasons have been the subject of controversy. I argue that the principal consideration in assessing these decisions ought to be the way in which the termination would affect the trial’s risk–benefit relationship. If there is not yet sufficient benefit to be gained from the study to offset the risks to which participants were exposed and it is expected that important scientific information would be obtained if the trial were continued, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Response to Commentators on “Examining the Potential Exploitation of UNOS Policies”.Sheldon Zink & Stacey Wertlieb - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (5):W15-W16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation