Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Bioethics and the problem of pluralism.Donald C. Ainslie - 2002 - Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (2):1-28.
    The state that we inhabit plays a significant role in shaping our lives. For not only do its institutions constrain the kinds of lives we can lead, but it also claims the right to punish us if our choices take us beyond what it deems to be appropriate limits. Political philosophers have traditionally tried to justify the state's power by appealing to their preferred theories of justice, as articulated in complex and wide-ranging moral theories—utilitarianism, Kantianism, and the like. One of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Bioethics And The Problem Of Pluralism.Donald Ainslie - 2002 - Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (2):1-28.
    The state that we inhabit plays a significant role in shaping our lives. For not only do its institutions constrain the kinds of lives we can lead, but it also claims the right to punish us if our choices take us beyond what it deems to be appropriate limits. Political philosophers have traditionally tried to justify the state's power by appealing to their preferred theories of justice, as articulated in complex and wide-ranging moral theories—utilitarianism, Kantianism, and the like. One of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Bioethics in a Multicultural World: Medicine and Morality in Pluralistic Settings. [REVIEW]Leigh Turner - 2003 - Health Care Analysis 11 (2):99-117.
    Current approaches in bioethics largely overlook the multicultural social environment within which most contemporary ethical issues unfold. For example, principlists argue that the common morality of society supports four basic ethical principles. These principles, and the common morality more generally, are supposed to be a matter of shared common sense. Defenders of case-based approaches to moral reasoning similarly assume that moral reasoning proceeds on the basis of common moral intuitions. Both of these approaches fail to recognize the existence of multiple (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • FRAMES OF COMPARISON Anthropology and Inheriting Traditional Practices.Thomas A. Lewis - 2005 - Journal of Religious Ethics 33 (2):225-253.
    This essay seeks to develop and illustrate an approach to comparison based on "ad hoc" frames. A frame is defined by a question, to which dif- ferent thinkers can be seen as offering complementary and/or competing responses. Pursuing a middle ground between universalist conceptions of comparison and particularist rejections of comparison, this approach brings various positions into dialogue in a manner that is not inherently totalizing. The article draws extensively on Hegel's philosophy of religion to articulate this approach to comparison (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Review of Jeffrey Stout: Ethics After Babel: The Languages of Morals and Their Discontents[REVIEW]Todd David Whitmore - 1989 - Ethics 100 (1):180-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Ethics After Babel: The Languages of Morals and Their Discontents.Jeffrey Stout - 2000 - Princeton University Press.
    A fascinating study of moral languages and their discontents, Ethics after Babel explains the links that connect contemporary moral philosophy, religious ethics, and political thought in clear, cogent, even conversational prose. Princeton's paperback edition of this award-winning book includes a new postscript by the author that responds to the book's noted critics, Stanley Hauerwas and the late Alan Donagan. In answering his critics, Jeffrey Stout clarifies the book's arguments and offers fresh reasons for resisting despair over the prospects of democratic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Democracy and Tradition.Jeffrey Stout - 2003 - Princeton University Press.
    Though responses to Stout's book, "Democracy and Tradition," have touched on his discussion of rights, none has comprehensively examined his position on the subject. Having endorsed several objections Stout raises against some influential views on democracy and rights, this article proceeds to criticize Stout's description and theoretical account of the natural and human rights traditions. The central argument is that Stout cannot successfully both affirm the traditions and adhere to his account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Buddhism and Bioethics. [REVIEW]Leslie Rezac & Damien Keown - 1998 - Hastings Center Report 28 (1):41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Morality, religion and metaphysics: Diverse visions in bioethics.Lisa M. Rasmussen - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (4):367 – 377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bioethics and Religions: Religious Traditions and Understandings of Morality, Health, and Illness.Leigh Turner - 2003 - Health Care Analysis 11 (3):181-197.
    For many individuals, religious traditions provide important resources for moral deliberation. While contemporary philosophical approaches in bioethics draw upon secular presumptions, religion continues to play an important role in both personal moral reasoning and public debate. In this analysis, I consider the connections between religious traditions and understandings of morality, medicine, illness, suffering, and the body. The discussion is not intended to provide a theological analysis within the intellectual constraints of a particular religious tradition. Rather, I offer an interpretive analysis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Approximation and Negotiation: Clinical Pragmatism and Difference.Joseph J. Fins - 1998 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 7 (1):68-76.
    When addressing cultural and religious differences in the clinical setting we need to be realists. Despite our public homage to pluralism and good intentions, it is just not possible to overcome all the differences that might exist and achieve perfect understanding of others. Try as we may, we will never be able to see perfectly the world through another's eyes. Instead of reaching for such perfection, we should instead reach for an approximation of shared understanding that will promote discourse and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Difference That Culture Can Make in End-of-Life Decisionmaking.H. Eugene Hern, Barbara A. Koenig, Lisa Jean Moore & Patricia A. Marshall - 1998 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 7 (1):27-40.
    Cultural difference has been largely ignored within bioethics, particularly within the end-of-life discourses and practices that have developed over the past two decades in the U.S. healthcare system. Yet how should culturebe taken into account?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Is pragmatism well-suited to bioethics?D. Micah Hester - 2003 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 28 (5 & 6):545 – 561.
    This paper attempts to defend pragmatic approaches to bioethics against detractors, showing how particular critics have failed or succeeded. The paper divides bioethics from a pragmatic point of view into three groups. The first group is called "bioethical pragmatism" that will be represented by two book-chapters from the anthology, Pragmatic Bioethics . The second group is called "clinical pragmatism" championed by Fins, Baccetta, and Miller. Finally, a third group, which has roots in the legal tradition, has been called "freestanding pragmatism" (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Clinical pragmatism: Bridging theory and practice.Joseph Fins, Franklin G. Miller & Matthew D. Bacchetta - 1998 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8 (1):37-42.
    : This response to Lynn Jansen's critique of clinical pragmatism concentrates on two themes: (1) contrasting approaches to moral epistemology and (2) the connection between theory and practice in clinical ethics. Particular attention is paid to the status of principles and the role of consensus, with some closing speculations on how Dewey might view the current state of bioethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Truth telling in medicine: The confucian view.Ruiping Fan & Benfu Li - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (2):179 – 193.
    Truth-telling to competent patients is widely affirmed as a cardinal moral and biomedical obligation in contemporary Western medical practice. In contrast, Chinese medical ethics remains committed to hiding the truth as well as to lying when necessary to achieve the family's view of the best interests of the patient. This essay intends to provide an account of the framing commitments that would both justify physician deception and have it function in a way authentically grounded in the familist moral concerns of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Principles of Biomedical Ethics.Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Tom L. Beauchamp & James F. Childress - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (4):37.
    Book reviewed in this article: Principles of Biomedical Ethics. By Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2214 citations  
  • A Thomistic understanding of human death.Jason T. Eberl - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (1):29–48.
    I investigate Thomas Aquinas's metaphysical account of human death, which is defined in terms of a rational soul separating from its material body. The question at hand concerns what criterion best determines when this separation occurs. Aquinas argues that a body has a rational soul only insofar as it is properly organised to support the soul's vegetative, sensitive, and rational capacities. According to the ‘higher‐brain’ concept of death, when a body can no longer provide the biological foundation necessary for the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the possibility of a pragmatic discourse bioethics: Putnam, Habermas, and the normative logic of bioethical inquiry.Elizabeth F. Cooke - 2003 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 28 (5 & 6):635 – 653.
    Pragmatic bioethics represents a novel approach to the discipline of bioethics, yet has met with criticisms which have beset the discipline of bioethics in the past. In particular, pragmatic bioethics has been criticized for its excessively fuzzy approach to fundamental questions of normativity, which are crucial to a field like bioethics. Normative questions need answers, and consensus is not always enough. The approach here is to apply elements of the discourse ethics of Habermas and Putnam to the sphere of bioethics, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Universalism & Particularism Fighting to a Draw.Daniel Callahan - 2000 - Hastings Center Report 30 (1):37-44.
    For decades now, moral philosophy and bioethics have been dominated variously by universalist and particularist impulses, both of which exert legitimate pull on our thinking. Although there is little prospect of settling the debate by recourse to theory, classifying the cases in which particularist and universalist demands compete reveals a rough practical guide.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What good is a pragmatic bioethic?Lisa Bellantoni - 2003 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 28 (5 & 6):615 – 633.
    Do bioethicists need yet another theoretical approach with which to frame their disagreements? Many pragmatists contend that pragmatism, unlike its liberal and utilitarian counterparts, is uniquely commendable in (a) beginning from our lived experiences and (b) locating those experiences amid our social relations. In place of an " principlism," pragmatism offers a practical "bedside-bioethic"; in lieu of "autonomy run amuk," pragmatism proposes an ethic rooted in our communal resources. To date, however, efforts to develop such a bioethic have been stymied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A theory of international bioethics: The negotiable and the non-negotiable.Robert Baker - 1998 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8 (3):233-273.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:A Theory of International Bioethics: The Negotiable and the Non-NegotiableRobert Baker (bio)AbstractThe preceding article in this issue of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal presents the argument that “moral fundamentalism,” the position that international bioethics rests on “basic” or “fundamental” moral principles that are universally accepted in all eras and cultures, collapses under a variety of multicultural and postmodern critiques. The present article looks to the contractarian tradition of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Comparative religious ethics and the problem of “human nature”.Aaron Stalnaker - 2005 - Journal of Religious Ethics 33 (2):187-224.
    Comparative religious ethics is a complicated scholarly endeavor, striving to harmonize intellectual goals that are frequently conceived as quite different, or even intrinsically opposed. Against commonly voiced suspicions of comparative work, this essay argues that descriptive, comparative, and normative interests may support rather than conflict with each other, depending on the comparison in question, and how it is pursued. On the basis of a brief comparison of the early Christian Augustine of Hippo and the early Confucians Mencius and Xunzi on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Ethics after Babel: The Languages of Morals and Their Discontents.Jeffrey Stout - 1993 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 33 (3):189-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Democracy and Tradition.Jeffrey Stout - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (2):287-310.
    Though responses to Stout's book, "Democracy and Tradition," have touched on his discussion of rights, none has comprehensively examined his position on the subject. Having endorsed several objections Stout raises against some influential views on democracy and rights, this article proceeds to criticize Stout's description and theoretical account of the natural and human rights traditions. The central argument is that Stout cannot successfully both affirm the traditions and adhere to his account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Democracy and Tradition.Jeffrey Stout - 2004 - American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 25 (2):185-190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations