Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (4 other versions)Rules and representations.Noam A. Chomsky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):1-15.
    The book from which these sections are excerpted is concerned with the prospects for assimilating the study of human intelligence and its products to the natural sciences through the investigation of cognitive structures, understood as systems of rules and representations that can be regarded as “mental organs.” These mental structui′es serve as the vehicles for the exercise of various capacities. They develop in the mind on the basis of an innate endowment that permits the growth of rich and highly articulated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1164 citations  
  • Intentional systems.Daniel C. Dennett - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (February):87-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   524 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.Gareth Evans & John Mcdowell - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (238):534-538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   706 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Inquiry.Robert C. Stalnaker - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (4):515-519.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   551 citations  
  • Beliefs and subdoxastic states.Stephen Stich - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (December):499-518.
    It is argued that the intuitively sanctioned distinction between beliefs and non-belief states that play a role in the proximate causal history of beliefs is a distinction worth preserving in cognitive psychology. The intuitive distinction is argued to rest on a pair of features exhibited by beliefs but not by subdoxastic states. These are access to consciousness and inferential integration. Harman's view, which denies the distinction between beliefs and subdoxastic states, is discussed and criticized.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   321 citations  
  • When Other Things Aren’t Equal: Saving Ceteris Paribus Laws from Vacuity.Paul Pietroski & Georges Rey - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (1):81-110.
    A common view is that ceteris paribus clauses render lawlike statements vacuous, unless such clauses can be explicitly reformulated as antecedents of ?real? laws that face no counterinstances. But such reformulations are rare; and they are not, we argue, to be expected in general. So we defend an alternative sufficient condition for the non-vacuity of ceteris paribus laws: roughly, any counterinstance of the law must be independently explicable, in a sense we make explicit. Ceteris paribus laws will carry a plethora (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Interpreted Logical Forms.Richard K. Larson & Peter Ludlow - 1993 - Synthese 95 (3):305 - 355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Demonstrative constructions, reference, and truth.Tyler Burge - 1974 - Journal of Philosophy 71 (7):205-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • What every speaker knows.Stephen P. Stich - 1971 - Philosophical Review 80 (4):476-496.
    The question I hope to answer is brief: What does every speaker of a natural language know? My answer is briefer still: Nothing, or at least nothing interesting. Explaining the question, and making the answer plausible, is a longer job.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Reply: Semantic theory and tacit knowledge.Gareth Evans - 1981 - In Steven H. Holtzman & Christopher M. Leich, Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule. Boston: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • A Defense of Derangement.Paul M. Pietroski - 1994 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):95 - 117.
    In a recent paper, Bar-On and Risjord (henceforth, 'B&R') contend that Davidson provides no 1 good argument for his (in)famous claim that "there is no such thing as a language." And according to B&R, if Davidson had established his "no language" thesis, he would thereby have provided a decisive reason for abandoning the project he has long advocated--viz., that of trying to provide theories of meaning for natural languages by providing recursive theories of truth for such languages. For he would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Chomsky's System of Ideas.G. R. Sampson & Fred D'Agostino - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (149):477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Mental causation for dualists.Paul M. Pietroski - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):336-366.
    The philosophical problem of mental causation concerns a clash between commonsense and scientific views about the causation of human behaviour. On the one hand, commonsense suggests that our actions are caused by our mental states—our thoughts, intentions, beliefs and so on. On the other hand, neuroscience assumes that all bodily movements are caused by neurochemical events. It is implausible to suppose that our actions are causally overdetermined in the same way that the ringing of a bell may be overdetermined by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Possible Worlds, Syntax, and Opacity.Paul M. Pietroski - 1993 - Analysis 53 (4):270 - 280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations