Switch to: Citations

References in:

Reflections on consequence

In Douglas Patterson (ed.), New essays on Tarski and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 263--299 (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Informal Rigour and Completeness Proofs.Georg Kreisel - 1967 - In Imre Lakatos (ed.), Problems in the philosophy of mathematics. Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co.. pp. 138--157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Truth in a Structure.Wilfrid Hodges - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86:135 - 151.
    Wilfrid Hodges; VIII*—Truth in a Structure, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986, Pages 135–152, https://doi.org/10.1093/ari.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The concept of logical consequence.William H. Hanson - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):365-409.
    In the first section, I consider what several logicians say informally about the notion of logical consequence. There is significant variation among these accounts, they are sometimes poorly explained, and some of them are clearly at odds with the usual technical definition. In the second section, I first argue that a certain kind of informal account—one that includes elements of necessity, generality, and apriority—is approximately correct. Next I refine this account and consider several important questions about it, including the appropriate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The Concept of Logical Consequence.William H. Hanson - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):365-409.
    In the first section, I consider what several logicians say informally about the notion of logical consequence. There is significant variation among these accounts, they are sometimes poorly explained, and some of them are clearly at odds with the usual technical definition. In the second section, I first argue that a certain kind of informal account—one that includes elements of necessity, generality, and apriority—is approximately correct. Next I refine this account and consider several important questions about it, including the appropriate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review: John Etchemendy, The Concept of Logical Consequence. [REVIEW]Vann Mcgee - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (1):254-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Tarski on truth and logical consequence.John Etchemendy - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):51-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Model-theoretic Semantics.John Etchemendy & Jon Barwise - 1989 - In Michael I. Posner (ed.), Foundations of Cognitive Science. MIT Press. pp. 207--243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Models, semantics and logical truth.John Etchemendy - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1):91 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Logical consequence: Models and modality.Stewart Shapiro - 1998 - In Matthias Schirn (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics Today: Papers From a Conference Held in Munich From June 28 to July 4,1993. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press. pp. 131--156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Heterogeneous logic.Jon Barwise & John Etchemendy - 1996 - In Gerard Allwein & Jon Barwise (eds.), Logical reasoning with diagrams. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Models and modality.Patricia A. Blanchette - 2000 - Synthese 124 (1-2):45-72.
    This paper examines the connection between model-theoretic truth and necessary truth. It is argued that though the model-theoretic truths of some standard languages are demonstrably ''''necessary'''' (in a precise sense), the widespread view of model-theoretic truth as providing a general guarantee of necessity is mistaken. Several arguments to the contrary are criticized.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Tarski on Logical Consequence.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 1996 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 37 (1):125-151.
    This paper examines from a historical perspective Tarski's 1936 essay, "On the concept of logical consequence." I focus on two main aims. The primary aim is to show how Tarski's definition of logical consequence satisfies two desiderata he himself sets forth for it: (1) it must declare logically correct certain formalizations of the -rule and (2) it must allow for variation of the individual domain in the test for logical consequence. My arguments provide a refutation of some interpreters of Tarski, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Formal and material consequence.Stephen Read - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (3):247 - 265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Logical consequence: A defense of Tarski.Greg Ray - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (6):617 - 677.
    In his classic 1936 essay "On the Concept of Logical Consequence", Alfred Tarski used the notion of satisfaction to give a semantic characterization of the logical properties. Tarski is generally credited with introducing the model-theoretic characterization of the logical properties familiar to us today. However, in his book, The Concept of Logical Consequence, Etchemendy argues that Tarski's account is inadequate for quite a number of reasons, and is actually incompatible with the standard model-theoretic account. Many of his criticisms are meant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • On the possibility of a privileged class of logical terms.Greg Ray - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 81 (2-3):303 - 313.
    Alfred Tarski's (1936) semantic account of the logical properties (logical consequence, logical truth and logical consistency) makes essential appeal to a distinction between logical and non-logical terms. John Etchemendy (1990) has recently argued that Tarski's account is inadequate for quite a number of different reasons. Among them is a brief argument which purports to show that Tarski's reliance on the distinction between logical and non-logical terms is in principle mistaken. According to Etchemendy, there are very simple (even first order) languages (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tarski and Carnap on Logical Truth: or: What Is Genuine Logic?Gerhard Schurz - 1999 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 6:77-94.
    I came to the topic of the title in connection with my logical investigations of the Is-Ought problem in multimodal logics . There are infinitely many mathematically possible modal logics. Are they all philosophically serious candidates? Which modal logic the “right” one — does such a question make sense? A similar question can be raised for the infinite variety of propositional logics weaker than classical logics. The Vienna Circle concept of logic was that logic holds merely by form, independently from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Etchemendy and Logical Consequence.Graham Priest - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):283 - 292.
    Logical consequence is a notion that every person who reasons must possess, at least implicitly. To give a precise and accurate characterization of this notion is the fundamental task of logic. In a similar way, the notion of effectivity is a concept that anyone with a basic training in mathematics possesses, and the most fundamental task of a theory of computability is to give a precise characterization of this notion. The problem concerning effectivity was solved in the 1930s, almost as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review: John Etchemendy, The Concept of Logical Consequence. [REVIEW]Vann McGee - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):379-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logical Consequence and Model-Theoretic Consequence.Greg O'Hair - 1992 - Logique Et Analyse 35:239-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation