Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A note on negation.CharlesB Daniels - 1990 - Erkenntnis 32 (3):423 - 429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Semantics for analytic containment.Fabrice Correia - 2004 - Studia Logica 77 (1):87-104.
    In 1977, R. B. Angell presented a logic for analytic containment, a notion of relevant implication stronger than Anderson and Belnap's entailment. In this paper I provide for the first time the logic of first degree analytic containment, as presented in [2] and [3], with a semantical characterization—leaving higher degree systems for future investigations. The semantical framework I introduce for this purpose involves a special sort of truth-predicates, which apply to pairs of collections of formulas instead of individual formulas, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • A story semantics for implication.Charles Daniels - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (2):221-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Multiple-conclusion lp and default classicality.Jc Beall - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):326-336.
    Philosophical applications of familiar paracomplete and paraconsistent logics often rely on an idea of . With respect to the paraconsistent logic LP (the dual of Strong Kleene or K3), such is standardly cashed out via an LP-based nonmonotonic logic due to Priest (1991, 2006a). In this paper, I offer an alternative approach via a monotonic multiple-conclusion version of LP.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • A Machine-Oriented Logic based on the Resolution Principle.J. A. Robinson - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):515-516.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • The logic of paradox.Graham Priest - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):219 - 241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   448 citations  
  • Analytic implication.Kit Fine - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (2):169-179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • On a New Idiom in the Study of Entailment.R. E. Jennings, Y. Chen & J. Sahasrabudhe - 2011 - Logica Universalis 5 (1):101-113.
    This paper is an experiment in Leibnizian analysis. The reader will recall that Leibniz considered all true sentences to be analytically so. The difference, on his account, between necessary and contingent truths is that sentences reporting the former are finitely analytic; those reporting the latter require infinite analysis of which God alone is capable. On such a view at least two competing conceptions of entailment emerge. According to one, a sentence entails another when the set of atomic requirements for the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Angellic Content.Kit Fine - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (2):199-226.
    I provide a truthmaker semantics for Angell’s system of analytic implication and establish completeness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Logics of Nonsense and Parry Systems.Thomas Macaulay Ferguson - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (1):65-80.
    We examine the relationship between the logics of nonsense of Bochvar and Halldén and the containment logics in the neighborhood of William Parry’s A I. We detail two strategies for manufacturing containment logics from nonsense logics—taking either connexive and paraconsistent fragments of such systems—and show how systems determined by these techniques have appeared as Frederick Johnson’s R C and Carlos Oller’s A L. In particular, we prove that Johnson’s system is precisely the intersection of Bochvar’s B 3 and Graham Priest’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • A computational interpretation of conceptivism.Thomas Macaulay Ferguson - 2014 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 24 (4):333-367.
    The hallmark of the deductive systems known as ‘conceptivist’ or ‘containment’ logics is that for all theorems of the form , all atomic formulae appearing in also appear in . Significantly, as a consequence, the principle of Addition fails. While often billed as a formalisation of Kantian analytic judgements, once semantics were discovered for these systems, the approach was largely discounted as merely the imposition of a syntactic filter on unrelated systems. In this paper, we examine a number of prima (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and 'coupled trees'.J. Michael Dunn - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 29 (3):149-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • A Kripke-style semantics for R-Mingle using a binary accessibility relation.J. Michael Dunn - 1976 - Studia Logica 35 (2):163 - 172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The completeness of S.Harry Deutsch - 1979 - Studia Logica 38 (2):137 - 147.
    The subsystem S of Parry's AI [10] (obtained by omitting modus ponens for the material conditional) is axiomatized and shown to be strongly complete for a class of three valued Kripke style models. It is proved that S is weakly complete for the class of consistent models, and therefore that Ackermann's rule is admissible in S. It also happens that S is decidable and contains the Lewis system S4 on translation — though these results are not presented here. S is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Grounding and truth-functions.Fabrice Correia - 2010 - Logique Et Analyse 53 (211):251-279.
    How does metaphysical grounding interact with the truth-functions? I argue that the answer varies according to whether one has a worldly conception or a conceptual conception of grounding. I then put forward a logic of worldly grounding and give it an adequate semantic characterisation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  • The logic of the catuskoti.Graham Priest - 2010 - Comparative Philosophy 1 (2):24-54.
    In early Buddhist logic, it was standard to assume that for any state of a ff airs there were four possibilities: that it held, that it did not, both, or neither. This is the catuskoti (or tetralemma). Classical logicians have had a hard time mak­ing sense of this, but it makes perfectly good sense in the se­mantics of various paraconsistent logics, such as First Degree Entailment. Matters are more complicated for later Buddhist thinkers, such as Nagarjuna, who appear to suggest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Three Systems of First Degree Entailment.Richard Bradshaw Angell - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations