Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Are quantum particles objects?Simon Saunders - 2006 - Analysis 66 (1):52-63.
    Particle indistinguishability has always been considered a purely quantum mechanical concept. In parallel, indistinguishable particles have been thought to be entities that are not properly speaking objects at all. I argue, to the contrary, that the concept can equally be applied to classical particles, and that in either case particles may (with certain exceptions) be counted as objects even though they are indistinguishable. The exceptions are elementary bosons (for example photons).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Primitive thisness and primitive identity.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (1):5-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   244 citations  
  • The ins and outs of counterfactual switching.Paul Teller - 2001 - Noûs 35 (3):365–393.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Identity, Modal Individuation, and Matter in Aristotle.Nicholas White - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 11 (1):475-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Exclusion principle and the identity of indiscernibles: A response to Margenau's argument.Michela Massimi - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (2):303--30.
    This paper concerns the question of whether Pauli's Exclusion Principle (EP) vindicates the contingent truth of Leibniz's Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles (PII) for fermions as H. Weyl first suggested with the nomenclature ‘Pauli–Leibniz principle’. This claim has been challenged by a time-honoured argument, originally due to H. Margenau and further articulated and champione by other authors. According to this argument, the Exclusion Principle—far from vindicating Leibniz's principle—would refute it, since the same reduced state, viz. an improper mixture, can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The exclusion principle and its philosophical importance.Henry Margenau - 1944 - Philosophy of Science 11 (4):187-208.
    It is strange to note so little discussion of the exclusion principle in the philosophical literature. Philosophers, largely engrossed in their perennial problems, are hardly aware of the fact that, during the last two decades, there has been introduced into physical methodology a principle of utmost philosophical importance, easily rivaling that of relativity and, in some respects, indeed that of causality. Discovered by Pauli in 1925, it immediately elucidated a whole realm of physical facts and was accepted by physicists with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Structural Realism and Contextual Individuality.John Stachel - 2005 - In ¸ Itebenmenahem:Hp. pp. 203--19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Handedness, parity violation, and the reality of space.Oliver Pooley - 2001 - In Katherine Brading & Elena Castellani (eds.), Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections. Cambridge University Press. pp. 250--280.
    In the first part of this paper a relational account of incongruent counterparts is defended against an argument due to Kant. I then consider a more recent attack on such an account, due to John Earman, which alleges that the relationalist cannot account for the lawlike left--right asymmetry manifested in parity-violating phenomena. I review Hoefer's, Huggett's and Saunders' responses to Earman's argument and argue that, while a relationalist account of parity-violating laws is possible, it comes at the cost of non-locality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations