Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Causes and Conditions.J. L. Mackie - 1965 - American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (4):245 - 264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   334 citations  
  • Hume's Sceptical Argument Against Reason.Fred Wilson - 1983 - Hume Studies 9 (2):90-129.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:HUME'S SCEPTICAL ARGUMENT AGAINST REASON In the section of the Treatise entitled Of scepticism with regard to reason Kume considers the mind as reflecting upon its own activities, monitors them as it were, and then adjusts them in accordance with certain principles and strategies. ^ What it discovers is that in drawing inferences, the mind sometimes errs. In the light of this knowledge, and in accordance with rational principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Testability and meaning (part 1).Rudolf Carnap - 1936 - Philosophy of Science 3 (4):420-71.
    Two chief problems of the theory of knowledge are the question of meaning and the question of verification. The first question asks under what conditions a sentence has meaning, in the sense of cognitive, factual meaning. The second one asks how we get to know something, how we can find out whether a given sentence is true or false. The second question presupposes the first one. Obviously we must understand a sentence, i.e. we must know its meaning, before we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  • Fact, Fiction, and Forecast.Nelson Goodman - 1973 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    In his new foreword to this edition, Hilary Putnam forcefully rejects these nativist claims.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1137 citations  
  • Testability and meaning.Rudolf Carnap - 1936 - Philosophy of Science 3 (4):419-471.
    Two chief problems of the theory of knowledge are the question of meaning and the question of verification. The first question asks under what conditions a sentence has meaning, in the sense of cognitive, factual meaning. The second one asks how we get to know something, how we can find out whether a given sentence is true or false. The second question presupposes the first one. Obviously we must understand a sentence, i.e. we must know its meaning, before we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   346 citations  
  • The Explanation Of Behaviour.C. Taylor - 1964 - Humanities Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   223 citations  
  • A Materialist Theory of the Mind.D. M. Armstrong - 1968 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Ted Honderich.
    Breaking new ground in the debate about the relation of mind and body, David Armstrong's classic text - first published in 1968 - remains the most compelling and comprehensive statement of the view that the mind is material or physical. In the preface to this new edition, the author reflects on the book's impact and considers it in the light of subsequent developments. He also provides a bibliography of all the key writings to have appeared in the materialist debate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   923 citations  
  • Dispositions, explanation, and behavior.Laird Addis - 1981 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 24 (2):205 – 227.
    According to the theory of dispositions here defended, to have a disposition is to have some (non-dispositional) property that enters into a law of a certain form. The theory does not have the crucial difficulty of the singular material implication account of dispositions, but at the same time avoids the unfortunate notion of 'reduction sentences'. It is further argued that no dispositional explanation is one of the covering-law type; but the theory shows how, for any dispositional explanation! To construct a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dispositions: Defined or reduced?Fred Wilson - 1969 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (2):184 – 204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dispositional properties.Herbert Hochberg - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (1):10-17.
    An analysis of problematic dispositional predicates like 'soluble' is presented. The analysis attempts to combine cogent features of opposed previous analyses of Carnap and Bergmann, while avoiding problematic features of both. The suggestion that there is an ambiguity in negations of assertions of dispositional properties, and a consequent distinction between "not soluble" and "insoluble," lies at the core of the solution.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Causal relations.Donald Davidson - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (21):691-703.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   335 citations  
  • Logic and professor Ryle.N. H. Colburn - 1954 - Philosophy of Science 21 (2):132-139.
    The period between 1945 and 1952 marked the development of Professor Ryle's conception of the principles of inference as performance rules. This development has paralleled that of his now well-known distinction between knowing-how and knowing-that. Indeed, the former is a corollary to the latter. Beginning with the inaugural address to the Aristotelian Society in 1945 and reaching full fruition in The Concept of Mind in 1949, it finds its most detailed and illuminating expression in “‘If’, ‘So’, and ‘Because’,” which appeared (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Book Review:The Concept of Physical Law Norman Swartz. [REVIEW]Fred Wilson - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (1):130-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Testability and meaning (part 2).Rudolf Carnap - 1937 - Philosophy of Science 4 (4):1-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   184 citations  
  • Explanation in Aristotle, Newton, and Toulmin: Part I.Fred Wilson - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (3):291-310.
    The claim that scientific explanation is deductive has been attacked on both systematic and historical grounds. This paper briefly defends the claim against the systematic attack. Essential to this defence is a distinction between perfect and imperfect explanation. This distinction is then used to illuminate the differences and similarities between Aristotelian (anthropomorphic) explanations of certain facts and those of classical mechanics. In particular, it is argued that when one attempts to fit classical mechanics into the Aristotelian framework the latter becomes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strawson's ontology.Gustav Bergmann - 1960 - Journal of Philosophy 57 (19):601-622.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Carnap and Goodman: Two Formalists.Alan Hausman & Fred Wilson - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (3):327-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Philosophy of science.Gustav Bergmann - 1977 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Dispositions and subjunctive conditionals, or, dormative virtues are no laughing matter.Elliott Sober - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (4):591-596.
    Philosophers frequently extract two lessons from Moliere's joke about the doctor who tried to explain why opium puts people to sleep by claiming that it has a dormative virtue. First, the principle I will call the equivalence thesis: attributions of dispositional properties are equivalent to certain associated subjunctive conditionals. The second is what I will call the reducibility thesis: for a dispositional concept to be nonproblematic, its “physical basis” must be found. In what follows, I will briefly describe three theoretical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Explanation, Causation and Deduction.Fred Wilson - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (2):311-313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Definition and discovery (I).Fred Wilson - 1967 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (4):43-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Moore and Ryle: Two Ontologists.L. C. Holborow - 1967 - Philosophical Quarterly 17 (67):175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations