Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1814 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Moral saints.Susan Wolf - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (8):419-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   392 citations  
  • Critique of Practical Reason.T. D. Weldon, Immanuel Kant & Lewis White Beck - 1949 - Philosophical Review 58 (6):625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   308 citations  
  • On the value of acting from the motive of duty.Barbara Herman - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (3):359-382.
    Richard Henson attempts to take the sting out of this view of Kant on moral worth by arguing (i) that attending to the phenomenon of the overdetermination of actions leads one to see that Kant might have had two distinct views of moral worth, only one of which requires the absence of cooperating inclinations, and (ii) that when Kant insists that there is moral worth only when an action is done from the motive of duty alone, he need not also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • (1 other version)Religion within the Limits of Reason alone.Immanuel Kant & Theodore M. Greene - 1936 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 43 (1):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • The Categorical Imperative.Stuart M. Brown & H. J. Paton - 1949 - Philosophical Review 58 (6):599 - 611.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Enlightenment, Revolution, and Romanticism: The Genesis of Modern German Political Thought, 1790–1800.Frederick C. Beiser - 1992 - Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • What Kant might have said: Moral worth and the overdetermination of dutiful action.Richard G. Henson - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (1):39-54.
    My purpose is to account for some oddities in what Kant did and did not say about "moral worth," and for another in what commentators tell us about his intent. The stone with which I hope to dispatch these several birds is-as one would expect a philosopher's stone to be-a distinction. I distinguish between two things Kant might have had in mind under the heading of moral worth. They come readily to mind when one both takes account of what he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Kant and the Claims of Taste.Eva Schaper - 1979 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 38 (2):198-200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Agent-centered restrictions from the inside out.Stephen Darwall - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 50 (3):291 - 319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Kant's Virtue Ethics: Robert B. Louden.Robert B. Louden - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (238):473 - 489.
    Among moral attributes true virtue alone is sublime. … [I]t is only by means of this idea [of virtue] that any judgment as to moral worth or its opposite is possible. … Everything good that is not based on a morally good disposition … is nothing but pretence and glittering misery. 1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason.J. Kemp - 1963 - Philosophical Quarterly 13 (50):82-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Moral worth.Paul Benson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (3):365 - 382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Does Kant's psychology of morality need basic revision?Richard Galvin - 1991 - Mind 100 (2):221-236.
    Any number of criticisms of Kant's moral psychology are directed at his claims that actions possessing moral worth must be performed "irrespective of all objects of the faculty of desire" (G 68,400),' and that actions done from duty must "set aside altogether the influence of inclination, and along with inclination every object of the will" (ibid). Rather than desire or inclination, it is "pure reverence for the law" that moves the will in actions done from duty (G 69,401). My present (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Kant on Moral Worth.Keith Simmons - 1989 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 6 (1):85 - 100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Idealism. [REVIEW]Arthur Melnick - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):134-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Motivation and Moral Choice in Kant’s Theory of Rational Agency.Richard McCarty - 1994 - Kant Studien 85 (1):15-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kant on Desire and Moral Pleasure.Mark Packer - 1989 - Journal of the History of Ideas 50 (3):429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kantian practical reason defended.Stephen L. Darwall - 1985 - Ethics 96 (1):89-99.
    There are two ways in which philosophical controversialists can approach a classical opponent of their views. They can attempt to refute him, or they can try to show that, while generally assumed to be an opponent, the philosopher really was not, at least when he was thinking clearly. Of these two strategies, the latter, if it can be pulled off, is dialectically..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Review of Onora O'Neill: Constructions of reason: explorations of Kant's practical philosophy[REVIEW]Stephen Engstrom - 1992 - Ethics 102 (3):653-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations