Switch to: Citations

References in:

Impossibility Arguments

In Michael Martin (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 199--214 (2007)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Omnipotence defined.Edward Wierenga - 1983 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 43 (3):363-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On an argument against omniscience.Keith Simmons - 1993 - Noûs 27 (1):22-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The problem of the essential indexical.John Perry - 1979 - Noûs 13 (1):3-21.
    Perry argues that certain sorts of indexicals are 'essential', in the sense that they cannot be eliminated in favor of descriptions. This paper also introduces the influential idea that certain sorts of indexicals play a special role in thought, and have a special connection to action.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   850 citations  
  • Divine omniscience and knowledge de se.Yujin Nagasawa - 2003 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 53 (2):73-82.
    Patrick Grim argues that God cannot beomniscient because no one other than me canacquire knowledge de se of myself. Inparticular, according to Grim, God cannot knowwhat I know in knowing that I am making amess. I argue, however, that given twoplausible principles regarding divineattributes there is no reason to accept Grim'sconclusion that God cannot be omniscient. Inthis paper I focus on the relationship betweendivine omniscience and necessaryimpossibilities, in contrast to the generaltrend of research since Aquinas, which hasconcentrated on the relationship (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Agency and omniscience.Tomis Kapitan - 1991 - Religious Studies 27 (1):105-120.
    It is said that faith in a divine agent is partly an attitude of trust; believers typically find assurance in the conception of a divine being's will, and cherish confidence in its capacity to implement its intentions and plans. Yet, there would be little point in trusting in the will of any being without assuming its ability to both act and know, and perhaps it is only by assuming divine omniscience that one can retain the confidence in the efficacy and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Omnipotence redux.Joshua Hoffman & Gary Rosenkrantz - 1988 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (2):283-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Omnipotence.Peter Geach - 1973 - Philosophy 48 (183):7-20.
    It is fortunate for my purposes that English has the two words ‘almighty’ and ‘omnipotent’, and that apart from any stipulation by me the words have rather different associations and suggestions. ‘Almighty’ is the familiar word that comes in the creeds of the Church; ‘omnipotent’ is at home rather in formal theological discussions and controversies, e.g. about miracles and about the problem of evil. ‘Almighty’ derives by way of Latin ‘omnipotens’ from the Greek word ‘ pantokratōr ’; and both this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Omniscience, Tensed Facts, and Divine Eternity.William Lane Craig - 2000 - Faith and Philosophy 17 (2):227--228.
    A difficulty for a view of divine eternity as timelessness is that if time is tensed, then God, in virtue of His omniscience, must know tensed facts. But tensed facts, such as It is now t, can only be known by a temporally located being.Defenders of divine atemporality may attempt to escape the force of this argument by contending either that a timeless being can know tensed facts or else that ignorance of tensed facts is compatible with divine omniscience. Kvanvig, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Omniscience, Tensed Facts, and Divine Eternity.William Lane Craig - 2000 - Faith and Philosophy 17 (2):225-241.
    A difficulty for a view of divine eternity as timelessness is that if time is tensed, then God, in virtue of His omniscience, must know tensed facts. But tensed facts, such as It is now t, can only be known by a temporally located being.Defenders of divine atemporality may attempt to escape the force of this argument by contending either that a timeless being can know tensed facts or else that ignorance of tensed facts is compatible with divine omniscience. Kvanvig, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Paradox of Omnipotence.J. L. Cowan - 1965 - Analysis 25 (Suppl-3):102-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Paradox of Omnipotence Revisited.J. L. Cowan - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3):435-445.
    A. Either God can create a stone which He cannot lift, or He cannot create a stone which He cannot lift. If God can create a stone which He cannot lift, then He is not omnipotent. If God cannot create a stone which He cannot lift, then He is not omnipotent. Therefore, God is not omnipotent.In a paper published in Analysis I tried to show that any attempt to find something wrong with all arguments of the general form of A (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Speaking of everything.Richard L. Cartwright - 1994 - Noûs 28 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Maximal Power.Thomas P. Flint & Alfred J. Freddoso - 1983 - In Alfred J. Freddoso (ed.), The Existence and Nature of God. University of Notre Dame Press. pp. 81--114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations