Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Natural Law and Moral Philosophy: From Grotius to the Scottish Enlightenment.Knud Haakonssen - 1996 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    This major contribution to the history of philosophy provides the most comprehensive guide to modern natural law theory available, sets out the full background to liberal ideas of rights and contractarianism, and offers an extensive study of the Scottish Enlightenment. The time span covered is considerable: from the natural law theories of Grotius and Suarez in the early seventeenth century to the American Revolution and the beginnings of utilitarianism. After a detailed survey of modern natural law theory, the book focuses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • (1 other version)An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue.Francis Hutcheson - 1726 - New York: Garland. Edited by Wolfgang Leidhold.
    Concerning beauty, order, harmony, design.--Concerning moral good and evil.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Freedom and Resentment.Peter Strawson - 1962 - Proceedings of the British Academy 48:187-211.
    The doyen of living English philosophers, by these reflections, took hold of and changed the outlook of a good many other philosophers, if not quite enough. He did so, essentially, by assuming that talk of freedom and responsibility is talk not of facts or truths, in a certain sense, but of our attitudes. His more explicit concern was to look again at the question of whether determinism and freedom are consistent with one another -- by shifting attention to certain personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1341 citations  
  • Adam Smith and self-interest.Eugene Heath - 2013 - In Christopher J. Berry, Maria Pia Paganelli & Craig Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Adam Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 241.
    The concepts of self-interest and self-love feature prominently in both The Theory of Moral Sentiments and The Wealth of Nations. Various notions of self-preservation, self-interest, and self-love are distinguished, and it is shown how self-love functions less as a motive than as an orientation. Although self-love may corrupt moral perception, the impartial spectator serves as an antidote. Smith’s conception of self-interest in The Wealth of Nations is a broad one and not inconsistent with the moral psychology of The Theory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Adam Smith on vanity, domination, and history.Daniel Luban - 2012 - Modern Intellectual History 9 (2):275-302.
    Adam Smith's lectures present a bleak theory of history in which the innate human results in the perpetuation of increasingly repressive slave societies. This theory challenges common conceptions about the philosophical and historical foundations of Smith's thought, and accounting for it requires moving beyond traditional dichotomies between an sphere grounded on asocial wants and a sphere grounded on sociability. For Smith, under the influence of earlier thinkers like La Rochefoucauld, Mandeville, and Rousseau, all human behavior is rooted in our esteem-seeking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Pufendorf on Natural Equality, Human Dignity, and Self-Esteem.Kari Saastamoinen - 2010 - Journal of the History of Ideas 71 (1):39-62.
    It is often maintained that Samuel Pufendorf founded natural equality on human dignity. This article partly questions this interpretation, maintaining that the dignity Pufendorf attributed to human nature did not indicate the Kantian idea of absolute and incomparable worth but only superiority in relation to other animals. This comparative dignity of humanity implied that all humans are equally obliged to obey natural law, but it did not offer a foundation for the similarity of their innate duties. The latter followed from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Smith's Humean criticism of Hume's account of the origin of justice.Spencer J. Pack & Eric Schliesser - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (1):47-63.
    It is argued that Adam Smith criticizes David Hume's account of the origin of and continuing adherence to the rule of law for being not sufficiently Humean. Hume explained that adherence to the rule of law originated in the self-interest to restrain self-interest. According to Smith, Hume does not pay enough attention to the passions of resentment and admiration, which have their source in the imagination. Smith's offers a more naturalistic and evolutionary account of the psychological pre-conditions of the establishment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Self, mind, and body.Peter F. Strawson - 1974 - In Peter Frederick Strawson (ed.), Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays. London, England: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Bringing the state to England: Andrew Tooke's translation of Samuel Pufendorf's 'De officio hominis et civis'.David Saunders & Ian Hunter - 2003 - History of Political Thought 24 (2):218-234.
    Andrew Tooke's 1691 English translation of Samuel Pufendorf's De officio hominis et civis, published as The Whole Duty of Man According to the Law of Nature, brought Pufendorf's manual fo statist natural law into English politics at a moment of temporary equilibrium in the unfinished contest between Crown and Parliament for the rights and powers of sovereignty. Drawing on the authors' re-edition of The Whole Duty of Man, this article describes and analyses a telling instance of how--by translation--the core political (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Existimatio: Unbescholtenheit Und Achtung Vor Dem Nebenmenschen Bei Kant Und In Der Kant Vorangehenden Naturrechtslehre.Joachim Hruschka - 2000 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 8.
    The article traces the origin of Kant's distinction between the right to a good name in the Doctrine of Right and the right to respect for human dignity in the Doctrine of Virtrue. The story begins with Pufendorf's distinction between existimatio simplex and existimatio intensiva. "Existimatio" for Pufendorf means "worth." Accordingly, existimatio simplex is plain human worth, whereas existimatio intensiva is the worth of dignitaries, meaning of persons who are ascribed special worth. For Thomasius and Barbeyrac "existimatio" becomes "respect." Existimatio (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pufendorf on Morality, Sociability, and Moral Powers.Stephen Darwall - 2012 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 50 (2):213-238.
    Only in the last twenty-five years have scholars begun to appreciate Samuel Pufendorf’s importance for the history of ethics. The signal element of Pufendorf’s ethics for recent commentators is his idea that morality arises when God imposes his superior will on a world that can contain no moral value of or on its own. But how, exactly, is “imposition” accomplished? According to Pufendorf, human beings do not simply defer to God in the way elephant seals do to a dominant male. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The political writings of Samuel Pufendorf.Samuel Pufendorf (ed.) - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This work presents the basic arguments and fundamental themes of the political and moral thought of the seventeenth-century philosopher, Samuel Pufendorf--one of the most widely read natural lawyers of the pre-Kantian era. Selections from the texts of Pufendorf's two major works, Elements of Universal Jurisprudence and The Law of Nature and of Nations, have been brought together to make Pufendorf's moral and political thought more accessible. The selections included have received a new English translation, the first for both works in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Protestant natural law theory: a general interpretation.K. Haakonssen - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pufendorf on Passions and Sociability.Heikki Haara - 2016 - Journal of the History of Ideas 77 (3):423-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz, Pufendorf, and the Possibility of Moral Self-Governance.Christopher Johns - 2013 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21 (2):281 - 301.
    (2013). Leibniz, Pufendorf, and the Possibility of Moral Self-Governance. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 21, No. 2, pp. 281-301. doi: 10.1080/09608788.2012.693064.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Natural Law and the Origin of Political Economy: Samuel Pufendorf and the History of Economics.Arild Sæther - 2017 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    Samuel Pufendorf's work on natural law and political economy was extensive and has been cited by several important figures in the history of economic thought. Yet his name is rarely mentioned in textbooks on the history of economic thought, the history of political science or the history of philosophy. In this unprecedented study, Arild Saether sheds new light both on Pufendorf's own life and work, as well as his influence on his contemporaries and on later scholars. This book explores Pufendorf (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Thomas Hobbes and the political philosophy of glory.Gabriella Slomp - 2000 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
    Hobbes's philosophical discourse is deconstructed as the interplay of the drama of individual behavior as perceived by rational agents and the detached analysis of conflict a by a political geometer . The author solves some long-standing problems in Hobbesian political philosophy (e.g., the role of glory, Hobbes' pessimism) and shows the consistency of Hobbes's attempt to derive absolutism as the only stable political association.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The morality of the fallen man: Samuel Pufendorf on natural law.Kari Saastamoinen - 1995 - Helsinki: SHS.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations