Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Hume's system. An examination of the First Book of his Treatise.David Pears - 1992 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 182 (1):82-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Whose Justice? Which Rationality?Alasdair Macintyre - 1988 - Journal of Religious Ethics 16 (2):363-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   392 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2001 citations  
  • What's Wrong with Monkish Virtues? Hume on the Standard of Virtue.Philip A. Reed - 2012 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 29 (1).
    How does Hume determine what qualities of the mind count as virtues and what qualities count as vices? By what standard, for example, does Hume dismiss the so-called “monkish virtues”? Hume’s commentators have proposed various possibilities for the standard of virtue, among them the general point of view and the usefulness/agreeableness of qualities. I consider the case for these standards and argue that Hume contends ultimately that consensus decides controversial questions about the status of virtues and vices. I try especially (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Does Moral Subjectivism Rest on a Mistake?Philippa Foot - 2002 - In Moral Dilemmas: And Other Topics in Moral Philosophy. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Foot examines the moral theory known as ‘non‐cognitivism’. Her central thesis is that all non‐cognitivist moral theories are based on the same serious mistake. This mistake is traced to a distinction taken for granted by non‐cognitivist moral philosophers such as A. J. Ayer and R. M. Hare. Such philosophers wrongly believed that there is a logical gap between ‘descriptive language’ and ‘evaluative language’. Foot argues that this supposed gap between facts and values, which crucially gives a logical gap between a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The naturalism of Hume (I.).Norman Smith - 1905 - Mind 14 (54):149-173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ethical Formation.Sabina Lovibond - 2002 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Sabina Lovibond invites her readers to see how the "practical reason view of ethics" can survive challenges from within philosophy and from the antirationalist postmodern critique of reason. She elaborates and defends a modern practical-reason view of ethics by focusing on virtue or ideal states of character that involve sensitivity to the objective reasons circumstances bring into play. At the heart of her argument is the Aristotelian idea of the formation of character through upbringing; these ancient ideas can be made (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Truth and Truthfulness An Essay in Genealogy.Bernard Williams - 2002 - Philosophy 78 (305):411-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   305 citations  
  • Leaving Nature Behind.Robert Pippin - 2002 - In Nicholas Hugh Smith (ed.), Reading McDowell: On Mind and World. New York: Routledge. pp. 58--75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The constraints of Hume’s naturalism.Barry Stroud - 2006 - Synthese 152 (3):339 - 351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The naturalism of Hume (II.).Norman Smith - 1905 - Mind 14 (55):335-347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Natural Virtues, Natural Vices: ANNETTE C. BAIER.Annette C. Baier - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 8 (1):24-34.
    David Hume has been invoked by those who want to found morality on human nature as well as by their critics. He is credited with showing us the fallacy of moving from premises about what is the case to conclusions about what ought to be the case; and yet, just a few pages after the famous is-ought remarks in A Treatise of Human Nature, he embarks on his equally famous derivation of the obligations of justice from facts about the cooperative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations