Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Negotiated or taken-for-granted trust? Explicit and implicit interpretations of trust in a medical setting.Helge Skirbekk - 2009 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 12 (1):3-7.
    Trust between a patient and a medical doctor is normally both justified and taken for granted, but sometimes it may need to be negotiated. In this paper I will present how trust can be interpreted as both an explicit and implicit phenomenon, drawing on literature from the social sciences and philosophy. The distinction between explicit and implicit interpretations of trust will be used to address problems that may arise in clinical consultations. Negotiating trust in any way very easily brings distrust (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In Death's Shadow: The Meanings of Withholding Resuscitation.Kathleen Nolan - 1987 - Hastings Center Report 17 (5):9-14.
    Many of the controversies surrounding the withholding of resuscitation are illuminated when we examine the language of resuscitation and resuscitative decisionmaking, and the contexts in which these decisions are made. Resuscitation and its withholding have multiple and often conflicting symbolic and emotional meanings for patients, families, and clinicians, and recognizing this divergence is essential to communication and to decisionmaking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Medical Futility and Physician Discretion.Michael Wreen - 2007 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 1 (3):257-267.
    Some patients have no chance of surviving if not treated, but very little chance if treated. A number of medical ethicists and physicians have argued that treatment in such cases is medically futile and a matter of physician discretion. This paper is a critical examination of that position. According to Howard Brody and others, a judgment of medical futility is a purely technical matter, and one which physicians are uniquely qualified to make. Although Brody later retracted these claims, he held (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the emotional character of trust.Bernd Lahno - 2001 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (2):171-189.
    Trustful interaction serves the interests of those involved. Thus, one could reason that trust itself may be analyzed as part of rational, goaloriented action. In contrast, common sense tells us that trust is an emotion and is, therefore, independent of rational deliberation to some extent. I will argue that we are right in trusting our common sense. My argument is conceptual in nature, referring to the common distinction between trust and pure reliance. An emotional attitude may be understood as some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Encounters with medical professionals: a crisis of trust or matter of respect? [REVIEW]Nina Hallowell - 2008 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11 (4):427-437.
    In this paper I shed light on the connection between respect, trust and patients’ satisfaction with their medical care. Using data collected in interviews with 49 women who had managed, or were in the process of managing, their risk of ovarian cancer using prophylactic surgery or ovarian screening, I examine their reported dissatisfaction with medical encounters. I argue that although many study participants appeared to mistrust their healthcare professionals’ (HCPs) motives or knowledge base, their dissatisfaction arose not from a lack (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Importance of Trust for Ethics, Law, and Public Policy.Mark A. Hall - 2005 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 14 (2):156-167.
    The importance of preserving trust in physicians and in medical institutions has received widespread attention in recent years. Primarily, this is due to the threats to trust posed by managed care, but there is a general and growing recognition that trust deserves more attention than it traditionally has received in all aspects of medical ethics, law, and public policy. Trust has both intrinsic and instrumental value. Trust is intrinsically important because it is a core characteristic that affects the emotional and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Futility has no utility in resuscitation medicine.M. Ardagh - 2000 - Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (5):396-399.
    “Futility” is a word which means the absence of benefit. It has been used to describe an absence of utility in resuscitation endeavours but it fails to do this. Futility does not consider the harms of resuscitation and we should consider the balance of benefit and harm that results from our resuscitation endeavours. If a resuscitation is futile then any harm that ensues will bring about an unfavourable benefit/harm balance. However, even if the endeavour is not futile, by any definition, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Choosing between life and death: Patient and family perceptions of the decision not to resuscitate the terminally ill cancer patient.Jaklin Eliott & Ian Olver - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (3):179–189.
    ABSTRACT In keeping with the pre‐eminent status accorded autonomy within Australia, Europe, and the United States, medical practice requires that patients authorize do‐not‐resuscitate (DNR) orders, intended to countermand the default practice in hospitals of instituting cardiopulmonary‐resuscitation (CPR) on all patients experiencing cardio‐pulmonary arrest. As patients typically do not make these decisions proactively, however, family members are often asked to act as surrogate decision‐makers and decide on the patient's behalf. Although the appropriateness of patients or their families having to decide about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Proxy consent: moral authority misconceived.A. Wrigley - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (9):527-531.
    The Mental Capacity Act 2005 has provided unified scope in the British medical system for proxy consent with regard to medical decisions, in the form of a lasting power of attorney. While the intentions are to increase the autonomous decision making powers of those unable to consent, the author of this paper argues that the whole notion of proxy consent collapses into a paternalistic judgement regarding the other person’s best interests and that the new legislation introduces only an advisor, not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Physicians' confidence in discussing do not resuscitate orders with patients and surrogates.D. P. Sulmasy, J. R. Sood & W. A. Ury - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (2):96-101.
    Purpose: Physicians are often reluctant to discuss “Do Not Resuscitate” orders with patients. Although perceived self-efficacy is a known prerequisite for behavioural change, little is understood about the confidence of physicians regarding DNR discussions.Subjects and methods: A survey of 217 internal medicine attendings and 132 housestaff at two teaching hospitals about their attitudes and confidence regarding DNR discussions.Results: Participants were significantly less confident about their ability to discuss DNR orders than to discuss consent for medical procedures , and this was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Trusting people.Annette C. Baier - 1992 - Philosophical Perspectives 6:137-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Supererogation and the profession of medicine.A. C. McKay - 2002 - Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (2):70-73.
    In the light of increasing public mistrust, there is an urgent need to clarify the moral status of the medical profession and of the relationship of the clinician to his/her patients. In addressing this question, I first establish the coherence, within moral philosophy generally, of the concept of supererogation . I adopt the notion of an act of “unqualified” supererogation as one that is non-derivatively good, praiseworthy, and freely undertaken for others' benefit at the risk of some cost to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Medical futility and physician discretion.M. Wreen - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (3):275-278.
    Some patients have no chance of surviving if not treated, but very little chance if treated. A number of medical ethicists and physicians have argued that treatment in such cases is medically futile and a matter of physician discretion. This paper critically examines that position.According to Howard Brody and others, a judgment of medical futility is a purely technical matter, which physicians are uniquely qualified to make. Although Brody later retracted these claims, he held to the view that physicians need (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations