Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristotle on Well-Being and Intellectual Contemplation.David Charles - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73:205-242.
    [David Charles] Aristotle, it appears, sometimes identifies well-being with one activity, sometimes with several, including ethical virtue. I argue that this appearance is misleading. In the Nicomachean Ethics, intellectual contemplation is the central case of human well-being, but is not identical with it. Ethically virtuous activity is included in human well-being because it is an analogue of intellectual contemplation. This structure allows Aristotle to hold that while ethically virtuous activity is valuable in its own right, the best life available for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Aristotle on Becoming Virtuous by Doing Virtuous Actions.Marta Jimenez - 2016 - Phronesis 61 (1):3-32.
    Aristotle ’s claim that we become virtuous by doing virtuous actions raises a familiar problem: How can we perform virtuous actions unless we are already virtuous? I reject deflationary accounts of the answer given in _Nicomachean Ethics_ 2.4 and argue instead that proper habituation involves doing virtuous actions with the right motive, i.e. for the sake of the noble, even though learners do not yet have virtuous dispositions. My interpretation confers continuity to habituation and explains in a non-mysterious way how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Aristotle on Corrective Justice.Thomas C. Brickhouse - 2014 - The Journal of Ethics 18 (3):187-205.
    This paper argues against the view favored by many contemporary scholars that corrective justice in the Nicomachean Ethics is essentially compensatory and in favor of a bifunctional account according to which corrective justice aims at equalizing inequalities of both goods and evils resulting from various interactions between persons. Not only does the account defended in this paper better explain the broad array of examples Aristotle provides than does the standard interpretation, it also better fits Aristotle’s general definition of what is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle on Eudaimonia.J. L. Ackrill - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 15-34.
    Originally published in Proceedings of the British Academy 60 (1974), 339-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • The Ugly, the Lonely, and the Lowly: Aristotle on Happiness and the External Goods.Matthew Cashen - 2012 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 29 (1).
    When he claims that it is hard to be happy when “exceedingly ugly, basely born, or alone and childless,” Aristotle introduces a notorious puzzle about his theory of happiness: if happiness is an activity of soul in accordance with virtue, why should appearance, family, and social life affect it? In this paper, I propose an answer to this puzzle. Against Martha Nussbaum, T.H. Irwin, and John Cooper, who maintain that “external goods” like beauty, health, and wealth, are constitutive parts of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Virtue and Reason in Plato and Aristotle.A. W. Price - 2011 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    A.W. Price explores the views of Plato and Aristotle on how virtue of character and practical reasoning enable agents to achieve eudaimonia--the state of living or acting well. He provides a full philosophical analysis and argues that the perennial question of action within human life is central to the reflections of these ancient philosophers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aristotle.Jennifer Whiting - 1986 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68 (1):70-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics".Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2005 - Princeton University Press.
    Gabriel Richardson Lear presents a bold new approach to one of the enduring debates about Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: the controversy about whether it coherently argues that the best life for humans is one devoted to a single activity, namely philosophical contemplation. Many scholars oppose this reading because the bulk of the Ethics is devoted to various moral virtues--courage and generosity, for example--that are not in any obvious way either manifestations of philosophical contemplation or subordinated to it. They argue that Aristotle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Aristotle on loving another for his own sake.Kelly Rogers - 1994 - Phronesis 39 (3):291-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Best Life for a Man.W. F. R. Hardie - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (207):35 - 50.
    Does Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics give one consistent answer to the question what life is best or two mutually inconsistent answers? In the First Book he says that we can agree to say that the best life is eudaimonia or eupraxia but must go on to say in what eudaimonia consists. By considering the specific nature of man as a thinking animal he reaches a conclusion: eudaimonia, the human good, is the activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Final Good in Aristotle's Ethics.W. F. R. Hardie - 1965 - Philosophy 40 (154):277-295.
    Aristotle maintains that every man has, or should have, a single end, a target at which he aims. The doctrine is stated in E.N. I 2. ‘If, then, there is some end of the things we do which we desire for its own sake, and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else, clearly this must be the good and the chief good. Will not the knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on life? Shall (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Aristotle on eudaimonia.J. L. Ackrill - 1975 - London: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Sovereign Virtue: Aristotle on the Relation Between Happiness and Prosperity.Stephen Augustus White - 1992 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    The central subject of Aristotle's ethics is happiness or living well. Most people in his day (as in ours), eager to enjoy life, impressed by worldly success, and fearful of serious loss, believed that happiness depends mainly on fortune in achieving prosperity and avoiding adversity. Aristotle, however, argues that virtuous conduct is the governing factor in living well and attaining happiness. While admitting that neither the blessings not the afflictions of fortune are unimportant, he maintains that the virtuous find life (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle on well-being and intellectual contemplation: Dominic Scott.Dominic Scott - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1):225–242.
    [David Charles] Aristotle, it appears, sometimes identifies well-being with one activity, sometimes with several, including ethical virtue. I argue that this appearance is misleading. In the Nicomachean Ethics, intellectual contemplation is the central case of human well-being, but is not identical with it. Ethically virtuous activity is included in human well-being because it is an analogue of intellectual contemplation. This structure allows Aristotle to hold that while ethically virtuous activity is valuable in its own right, the best life available for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves.Jennifer Whiting - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):270-290.
    Aristotle's requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle's requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle's apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle's account of loving a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Human Good.Richard Kraut - 1989 - Princeton University Press.
    Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, which equates the ultimate end of human life with happiness, is thought by many readers to argue that this highest goal consists in the largest possible aggregate of intrinsic goods. Richard Kraut proposes instead that Aristotle identifies happiness with only one type of good: excellent activity of the rational soul. In defense of this reading, Kraut discusses Aristotle's attempt to organize all human goods into a single structure, so that each subordinate end is desirable for the sake (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy.Martha C. Nussbaum - 1986 - Phronesis 32 (1):101-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   331 citations  
  • Aristotle on Virtue and Happiness.Julia Annas & Hsin-li Wang - 1989 - Philosophy and Culture 35 (4):157-170.
    Author Julia Annas Aristotle made ​​the German Asia-mile out and fortunately Fuk The arguments related point, and the role of external good fortune Fook in the problems caused. And text analysis and dialectical Happy Stoic school and school for good moral behavior and external point of view. Author argues, Aristotle on the German sub-km behavior regardless of the state with the fortunate Fook, reflecting the hope臘human ethics ideological consensus, and he left to posterity to resolve the discovery. Aristotle on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Permanent Happiness: Aristotle and Solon.Terence H. Irwin - 1985 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3:89-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Aristotle and Protagoras: The Good Human Being as the Measure of Goods.Paula Gottlieb - 1991 - Apeiron 24 (1):25 - 45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Rationality, Eudaimonia and Kakodaimonia in Aristotle.Robert Heinaman - 1993 - Phronesis 38 (1):31-56.
    I argue that Aristotle does not believe all rational action aims at securing eudaimonia (happiness) for the agent. Intrinsic goods are worth having independently of their promotion of any further ends, including eudaimonia. Aiming for such a good or avoiding evil may be rational even when eudaimonia is impossible and not the agent's goal. "Politics" 1332a7f suggests that even the happy agent may act rationally without aiming for eudaimonia. The final section argues that, given that an immoral agent secures the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Aristotle on the Human Good.Richard KRAUT - 1989 - Philosophy 66 (256):246-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Aristotle on the Human Good.Richard KRAUT - 1989 - Ethics 101 (2):382-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Eudaimonia as an activity in nicomachean ethics 1. 8–12.Robert Heinaman - 2007 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 33:221-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Eudaimonia and Self-sufficiency in the Nicomachean Ethics.Robert Heinaman - 1988 - Phronesis 33 (1):31-53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books Ii--Iv: Translated with an Introduction and Commentary.C. C. W. Taylor - 2006 - Oxford University Press UK.
    This volume, which is part of the Clarendon Aristotle Series, offers a clear and faithful new translation of Books II to IV of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, accompanied by an analytical commentary focusing on philosophical issues. In Books II to IV, Aristotle gives his account of virtue of character in general and of the principal virtues individually, topics of central interest both to his ethical theory and to modern ethical theorists. Consequently major themes of the commentary are connections on the one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Practices of Reason: Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics.C. D. C. REEVE - 1992 - Philosophical Review 103 (3):567-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Aristotle on the goods of fortune.John M. Cooper - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (2):173-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Aristotle's Inclusivism.Roger Crisp - 1994 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12:111-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aristotle.C. C. W. Taylor - 2010 - In John Skorupski (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Ethics. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle On Well-Being And Intellectual Contemplation: Dominic Scott.Dominic Scott - 1999 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73 (1):225-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Precarious virtue. [REVIEW]Sophie Botros - 1987 - Phronesis 32 (1):101-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations