Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. ‘Moral Particularism: Wrong and Bad’.Brad Hooker - 2000 - In Brad Hooker & Margaret Olivia Little (eds.), Moral particularism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Ethics as an inexact science: Aristotle's ambitions for moral theory'.Terence H. Irwin - 2000 - In Brad Hooker & Margaret Olivia Little (eds.), Moral particularism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 100--29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Ethica Nicomachea.W. D. Aristotle & Ross - 1894 - Clarendon Press. Edited by J. Bywater.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Moral Reasons.Mark Van Roojen - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):118-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Ethics without principles.Jonathan Dancy - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this much-anticipated book, Jonathan Dancy offers the only available full-scale treatment of particularism in ethics, a view with which he has been associated for twenty years. Dancy now presents particularism as the view that the possibility of moral thought and judgement does not in any way depend on an adequate supply of principles. He grounds this claim on a form of reasons-holism, holding that what is a reason in one case need not be any reason in another, and maintaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   657 citations  
  • Dilemmas.Milton H. Williams - 1956 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 16 (4):563-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • A Defense of Aristotle’s Doctrine that Virtue Is a Mean.Howard J. Curzer - 1996 - Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):129-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ethics without reasons?Roger Crisp - 2007 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 4 (1):40-49.
    This paper is a discussion of Jonathan Dancy's book Ethics Without Principles (2004). Holism about reasons is distinguished into a weak version, which allows for invariant reasons, and a strong, which doesn't. Four problems with Dancy's arguments for strong holism are identified. (1) A plausible particularism based on it will be close to generalism. (2) Dancy rests his case on common-sense morality, without justifying it. (3) His examples are of non-ultimate reasons. (4) There are certain universal principles it is hard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Morality and virtue: An assessment of some recent work in virtue ethics.David Copp & David Sobel - 2004 - Ethics 114 (3):514-554.
    This essay focuses on three recent books on morality and virtue, Michael Slote's 'Morals from Motives', Rosalind Hursthouse's 'On Virtue Ethics', and Philippa Foot's 'Natural Goodness'. Slote proposes an "agent-based" ethical theory according to which the ethical status of acts is derivative from assessments of virtue. Following Foot's lead, Hursthouse aims to vindicate an ethical naturalism that explains human goodness on the basis of views about human nature. Both Hursthouse and Slote take virtue to be morally basic in a way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Reason and human good in Aristotle.John Madison Cooper - 1975 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    I Deliberation, Practical Syllogisms , and Intuition. Introduction Aristotle's views on moral reasoning are a difficult and much disputed subject. ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Contemplation and happiness: A reconsideration.John M. Cooper - 1987 - Synthese 72 (2):187 - 216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Aristotle's Philosophy of Action.T. H. Irwin - 1986 - Phronesis 31 (1):68-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Philosophy of Action.David Charles - 1984 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • De anima II 5.Myles F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28-90.
    This is a close scrutiny of De Anima II 5, led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming like (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Aristotle's republic or, why Aristotle's ethics is not virtue ethics.Stephen Buckle - 2002 - Philosophy 77 (4):565-595.
    Modern virtue ethics is commonly presented as an alternative to Kantian and utilitarian views—to ethics focused on action and obligations—and it invokes Aristotle as a predecessor. This paper argues that the Nichomachean Ethics does not represent virtue ethics thus conceived, because the discussion of the virtues of character there serves a quasi-Platonic psychology: it is an account of how to tame the unruly (non-rational) elements of the human soul so that they can be ruled by reason and the laws it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What is “the mean relative to us” in Aristotle's Ethics?”.Lesley Brown - 1997 - Phronesis 42 (1):77-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5.John Bowin - 2011 - Phronesis 56 (2):138-161.
    In De Anima II 5, 417a21-b16, Aristotle makes a number of distinctions between types of transitions, affections, and alterations. The objective of this paper is to sort out the relationships between these distinctions by means of determining which of the distinguished types of change can be coextensive and which cannot, and which can overlap and which cannot. From the results of this analysis, an interpretation of 417a21-b16 is then constructed that differs from previous interpretations in certain important respects, chief among (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Pleasure and Activity in Aristotle's Ethics.David Bostock - 1988 - Phronesis 33 (1):251-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Book Review: Unprincipled Virtue by Nomy Arpaly. [REVIEW]Manuel Vargas - 2003 - The Journal of Ethics 8 (2):201-204.
    Nomy Arpaly rejects the model of rationality used by most ethicists and action theorists. Both observation and psychology indicate that people act rationally without deliberation, and act irrationally with deliberation. By questioning the notion that our own minds are comprehensible to us--and therefore questioning much of the current work of action theorists and ethicists--Arpaly attempts to develop a more realistic conception of moral agency.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Virtue ethics and the charge of egoism.Julia Annas - 2008 - In Paul Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest. New York: Oxford University Press.
    There are problems with egoism as a theory, but what matters here is the point that intuitively ethics is thought to be about the good of others, so that focusing on your own good seems wrong from the start. Virtues are not just character traits, however, since forgetfulness or stubbornness are not virtues. Virtues are character traits which are in some way desirable. Criticism is generally renewed at this point on the grounds that claims about flourishing are now including claims (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • The phenomenology of virtue.Julia Annas - 2008 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (1):21-34.
    What is it like to be a good person? I examine and reject suggestions that this will involve having thoughts which have virtue or being a good person as part of their content, as well as suggestions that it might be the presence of feelings distinct from the virtuous person’s thoughts. Is there, then, anything after all to the phenomenology of virtue? I suggest that an answer is to be found in looking to Aristotle’s suggestion that virtuous activity is pleasant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Aristotle on action.John L. Ackrill - 1976 - Mind 87 (348):595-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • 2. Aristotle on Eudaimonia.J. L. Ackrill - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 15-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Doing and being: an interpretation of Aristotle's Metaphysics theta.Jonathan B. Beere - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Doing and Being confronts the problem of how to understand two central concepts of Aristotle's philosophy: energeia and dunamis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta.Jonathan B. Beere - 2009 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Doing and Being confronts the problem of how to understand two central concepts of Aristotle's philosophy: energeia and dunamis. While these terms seem ambiguous between actuality/potentiality and activity/capacity, Aristotle did not intend them to be so. Through a careful and detailed reading of Metaphysics Theta, Beere argues that we can solve the problem by rejecting both "actuality" and "activity" as translations of energeia, and by working out an analogical conception of energeia. This approach enables Beere to discern a hitherto unnoticed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • From morality to virtue.Michael Slote - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Roger Crisp & Michael A. Slote.
    In this book, Slote offers the first full-scale foundational account of virtue ethics to have appeared since the recent revival of interest in the ethics of virtue. Slote advocates a particular form of such ethics for its intuitive and structural advantages over Kantianism, utilitarianism, and common-sense morality, and he argues that the problems of other views can be avoided and a contemporary plausible version of virtue ethics achieved only by abandoning specifically moral concepts for general aretaic notions like admirability and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?Martha C. Nussbaum - 1999 - The Journal of Ethics 3 (3):163-201.
    Virtue ethics is standardly taught and discussed as a distinctive approach to the major questions of ethics, a third major position alongside Utilitarian and Kantian ethics. I argue that this taxonomy is a confusion. Both Utilitarianism and Kantianism contain treatments of virtue, so virtue ethics cannot possibly be a separate approach contrasted with those approaches. There are, to be sure, quite a few contemporary philosophical writers about virtue who are neither Utilitarians nor Kantians; many of these find inspiration in ancient (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Aristotle on Virtue: Wrong, Wrong, and Wrong.Thomas Hurka - 2012 - In Julia Peters (ed.), Aristotelian Ethics in Contemporary Perspective. New York: Routledge. pp. 9-26.
    In his chapter ‘Aristotle on Virtue: Wrong, Wrong, and Wrong’, Thomas Hurka advances penetrating criticisms of some of the core theses of the Aristotelian approach to virtue. Hurka challenges the Aristotelian tendency to blur the distinction between the good and the right by making the virtues, which are constitutive of a person’s goodness, objects of praise or blame. He puts into question the Aristotelian doctrine of the mean and the idea that vice can always be explained in terms of either (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Virtue, Vice and Value.Thomas Hurka - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208):413-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Distinction between Energeia and Kinesis.J. L. Ackrill - 1965 - In R. Bambrough ed (ed.), New Essays on Plato and Aristotle. Routledge. pp. 121-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • 18. The Good Man and the Good for Man in Aristotle's Ethics.Kathleen V. Wilkes - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 341-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Role of Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Ethics'.John McDowell - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 359--76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • 19. The Role of Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Ethics.John McDowell - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 359-376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View.Christine Swanton - 2006 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 31:75-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • Dilemmas.Gilbert Ryle - 1954 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    These two puzzles were classic if academic examples of the dilemmas Professor Ryle is concerned with.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Human Good.Richard Kraut - 1989 - Princeton University Press.
    Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, which equates the ultimate end of human life with happiness, is thought by many readers to argue that this highest goal consists in the largest possible aggregate of intrinsic goods. Richard Kraut proposes instead that Aristotle identifies happiness with only one type of good: excellent activity of the rational soul. In defense of this reading, Kraut discusses Aristotle's attempt to organize all human goods into a single structure, so that each subordinate end is desirable for the sake (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • The Aristotelian ethics: a study of the relationship between the Eudemian and Nicomachean ethics of Aristotle.Anthony Kenny - 1978 - Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press.
    A study of the relationship between the Eudemian and Nichomachean Ethics of Aristotle.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge.William P. Alston - 1996 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 60 (1):197-201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aristotle.Jennifer Whiting - 1986 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68 (1):70-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves.Jennifer Whiting - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):270-290.
    Aristotle's requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle's requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle's apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle's account of loving a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Eudaimonia, External Results, and Choosing Virtuous Actions for Themselves.Jennifer Whiting - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):270-290.
    Aristotle’s requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle’s requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle’s apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle’s account of loving a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Socrates, ironist and moral philosopher.Gregory Vlastos - 1991 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Putnam discusses each of the fifteen odes found in the book, studying the work both as a whole and as a series of interactive units.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Review of Moral Particularism (ed. Brad Hooker and Margaret Little). [REVIEW]Pekka Väyrynen - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):478-483.
    This is a short review of Moral Particularism, ed. Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (Oxford University Press, 2002).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • The Structure of Aristotelian Happiness:Aristotle on the Human Good. Richard Kraut.T. H. Irwin - 1991 - Ethics 101 (2):382-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Nicomachean Ethics.C. C. W. Taylor - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (2):247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Notes on the Nichomachean Ethics of Aristotle.J. Stewart - 1893 - Philosophical Review 2:120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Review of Nancy Sherman: The Fabric of Character: Aristotle's Theory of Virtue[REVIEW]C. D. C. Reeve - 1990 - Ethics 100 (4):894-895.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The fabric of character: Aristotle's theory of virtue.Nancy Sherman - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Most traditional accounts of Aristotle's theory of ethical education neglect its cognitive aspects. This book asserts that, in Aristotle's view, excellence of character comprises both the sentiments and practical reason. Sherman focuses particularly on four aspects of practical reason as they relate to character: moral perception, choicemaking, collaboration, and the development of those capacities in moral education. Throughout the book, she is sensitive to contemporary moral debates, and indicates the extent to which Aristotle's account of practical reason provides an alternative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • The structure of Aristotle's ethical theory: Is it teleological or a virtue ethics?Gerasimos Santas - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):59-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on loving another for his own sake.Kelly Rogers - 1994 - Phronesis 39 (3):291-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations