Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Thought and talk.Donald Davidson - 1975 - In Samuel D. Guttenplan (ed.), Mind and language. Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. pp. 1975--7.
    What is the connection between thought and language? The dependence of speaking on thinking is evident, for to speak is to express thoughts. This dependence is manifest in endless further ways. Someone who utters the sentence “The candle is out” as a sentence of English must intend to utter words that are true if and only if an indicated candle is out at the time of utterance, and he must believe that by making the sounds he does he is uttering (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   310 citations  
  • On being morally considerable.Kenneth E. Goodpaster - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (6):308-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • All Animals Are Equal.Peter Singer - 1989 - In Tom Regan & Peter Singer (eds.), Animal Rights and Human Obligations. Cambridge University Press. pp. 215--226.
    In recent years a number of oppressed groups have campaigned vigorously for equality. The classic instance is the Black Liberation movement, which demands an end to the prejudice and discrimination that has made blacks second-class citizens. The immediate appeal of the black liberation movement and its initial, if limited, success made it a model for other oppressed groups to follow. We became familiar with liberation movements for Spanish-Americans, gay people, and a variety of other minorities. When a majority group—women—began their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Virtue Theory and Abortion.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1991 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (3):223-246.
    The sort of ethical theory derived from Aristotle, variously described as virtue ethics, virtue-based ethics, or neo-Aristotelianism, is becoming better known, and is now quite widely recognized as at least a possible rival to deontological and utilitarian theories. With recognition has come criticism, of varying quality. In this article I shall discuss nine separate criticisms that I have frequently encountered, most of which seem to me to betray an inadequate grasp either of the structure of virtue theory or of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Cogito, ergo sum: Inference or performance?Jaakko Hintikka - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (1):3-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • The ethics of respect for nature.Paul W. Taylor - 1981 - Environmental Ethics 3 (3):197-218.
    I present the foundational structure for a life-centered theory of environmental ethics. The structure consists of three interrelated components. First is the adopting of a certain ultimate moral attitude toward nature, which I call “respect for nature.” Second is a belief system that constitutes a way of conceiving of the natural world and of our place in it. This belief system underlies and supports the attitude in a way that makes it an appropriate attitude to take toward the Earth’s natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Environmental ethics and weak anthropocentrism.Bryan G. Norton - 1984 - Environmental Ethics 6 (2):131-148.
    The assumption that environmental ethics must be nonanthropocentric in order to be adequate is mistaken. There are two forms of anthropocentrism, weak and strong, and weak anthropocentrism is adequate to support an environmental ethic. Environmental ethics is, however, distinctive vis-a-vis standard British and American ethical systems because, in order to be adequate, it must be nonindividualistic.Environmental ethics involves decisions on two levels, one kind of which differs from usual decisions affecting individual fairness while the other does not. The latter, called (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Is There a Need for a New, an Environmental Ethic.Richard Routley - 1973 - Proceedings of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy 1:205-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Meaning and speech acts.R. M. Hare - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (1):3-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Meaning and speech acts.John R. Searle - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (4):423-432.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Virtue Theory and Abortion.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1997 - In Roger Crisp & Michael Slote (eds.), Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.
    The sort of ethical theory derived from Aristotle, variously described as virtue ethics, virtue-based ethics, or neo-Aristotelianism, is becoming better known, and is now quite widely recognized as at least a possible rival to deontological and utilitarian theories. With recognition has come criticism, of varying quality. In this article I shall discuss nine separate criticisms that I have frequently encountered, most of which seem to me to betray an inadequate grasp either of the structure of virtue theory or of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • (1 other version)Eating Meat and Eating People.Cora Diamond & Kenan Professor - 2004 - In Cass R. Sunstein & Martha Craven Nussbaum (eds.), Animal rights: current debates and new directions. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Reason and feeling in thinking about justice.Susan Moller Okin - 1989 - Ethics 99 (2):229-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Justice, care, and gender: The Kohlberg-Gilligan debate revisited.Owen Flanagan & Kathryn Jackson - 1987 - Ethics 97 (3):622-637.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Applying virtue ethics.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1995 - In Rosalind Hursthouse, Gavin Lawrence & Warren Quinn (eds.), Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory: Essays in Honour of Philippa Foot. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 57--75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Rights.H. J. McCloskey - 1965 - Philosophical Quarterly 15 (59):115-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The good of trees.Robin Attfield - 1981 - Journal of Value Inquiry 15 (1):35-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Is There a Moral Obligation to Have Children?Saul Smilansky - 1995 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 12 (1):41-53.
    ABSTRACT I argue, counter‐intuitively, that under certain conditions many people are under some moral requirement to attempt to bring children into being . There is only rarely a strict obligation to have children, but more moderate, inclining moral considerations in favour of having children, have a place in our moral world. I begin by considering a large number of arguments in favour and against the possibility of an obligation to have children. Then I examine when the weight of one set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Do Animals Have a Right to Liberty.James Rachels - 1989 - In Tom Regan & Peter Singer (eds.), Animal Rights and Human Obligations. Cambridge University Press. pp. 205-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Rawlsian resources for animal ethics.Ruth Abbey - 2007 - Ethics and the Environment 12 (1):1-22.
    : This article considers what contribution the work of John Rawls can make to questions about animal ethics. It argues that there are more normative resources in A Theory of Justice for a concern with animal welfare than some of Rawls's critics acknowledge. However, the move from A Theory of Justice to Political Liberalism sees a depletion of normative resources in Rawlsian thought for addressing animal ethics. The article concludes by endorsing the implication of A Theory of Justice that we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Women, Morality, and History.Linda Nicholson - 1983 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Are mere things morally considerable?W. Murray Hunt - 1980 - Environmental Ethics 2 (1):59-65.
    Kenneth Goodpaster has criticized ethicists like Feinberg and Frankena for too narrowly circumscribing the range of moral considerability, urging instead that “nothing short of the condition of being alive” is a satisfactory criterion. Goodpaster overlooks at least one crucial objection: that his own “condition of being alive” may aIso be too narrow a criterion of moral considerability, since “being in existence” is at least as plausible and nonarbitrary a criterion as is Goodpaster’s. I show that each of the arguments that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Reasonable Partiality and Animal Ethics.Bernard E. Rollin - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2):105-121.
    Moral psychology is often ignored in ethical theory, making applied ethics difficult to achieve in practice. This is particularly true in the new field of animal ethics. One key feature of moral psychology is recognition of the moral primacy of those with whom we enjoy relationships of love and friendship – philia in Aristotles term. Although a radically new ethic for animal treatment is emerging in society, its full expression is severely limited by our exploitative uses of animals. At this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Introduction.Tom Regan - 1980 - In Tom L. Beauchamp & Tom Regan (eds.), Matters of life and death. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)On stopping at everything: A reply to W. M. hunt.Kenneth E. Goodpaster - 1980 - Environmental Ethics 2 (3):281-284.
    Contrary to W. Murray Hunt’s suggestion, living things deserve moral consideration and inanimate objects do not precisely because living things can intelligibly be said to have interests (and inanimate objects cannot intelligibly said to have interests). Interests are crucial because the concept of morality is noncontingently related to beneficence or nonmaleficence, notions which misfire completely in theabsence of entities capable of being benefited or harmed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Beasts Versus the Biosphere?Mary Midgley - 1992 - Environmental Values 1 (2):113 - 121.
    Apparent clashes of interest between 'deep ecologists' and 'animal liberationists' can be understood as differences in emphasis rather than conflicts of principle, although it is only too easy for campaigners to regard as rivals good causes other than their own. Moral principles are part of a larger whole, within which they can be related, rather than absolute all-purpose rules of right conduct. This is illustrated using the practical dilemma which often occurs in conservation management, of whether or not to cull (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • McCloskey on why animals cannot have rights.Tom Regan - 1976 - Philosophical Quarterly 26 (104):251-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Anthropocentrism, Atomism, and Environmental Ethics.Donald Scherer - 1982 - Environmental Ethics 4 (2):115-123.
    By attempting to divorce attributions of value from judgments of the interest of the attributor, developing the concept ofa locus of value, exploring the interconnections between the goods of individuals and the goods of populations and species, and suggesting the reasonableness ofthe attributions of rights to certain sorts of individuals, I try to indicate the degree to which an environmental ethic can be atomisticwithout being anthropocentric.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • If Horses Had Hands ….Tom Tyler - 2003 - Society and Animals 11 (3):267-281.
    This paper examines the contentious and confused notion of anthropomorphism. Beginning with an overview of the term's etymology and present use, it examines the arguments of those who believe it to be unscientific and demeaning, and those who believe it to be an inevitable and useful pragmatic strategy. The German philosopher Heidegger raises the more serious objection, though, that as a concept anthropomorphism is not even meaningful. Supplementing his argument with examples drawn from evolutionary theory and elsewhere, the paper concludes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Context-dependence in human and animal communication.Pietro Perconti - 2002 - Foundations of Science 7 (3):341-362.
    The aim of this paper is to show that humanlanguage is context-dependent in a veryspecific way. In order to support this thesis,a detailed comparison is made between the waysin which verbal expressions depend on thecontext of occurrence and evaluation and animalcommunication systems. The comparisonhighlights a series of analogies anddifferences between human language and thecommunication systems of other animals. Myproposal is to use the term `indexicality' toindicate the characteristic way of using thecontext in human language and to use the moregeneral phrase (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Animal thoughts.Raimond Gaita - 1992 - Philosophical Investigations 15 (3):227-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intrinsic value and direct duties: From animal ethics towards environmental ethics? [REVIEW]Robert Heeger & Frans W. A. Brom - 2001 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 14 (2):241-252.
    Three types of concern for animal welfare are widelyheld: Animals should feel well, they should function well, andthey should lead natural lives. The paper deals with a well-knownanswer to the question of why such concerns are morallyappropriate: Human beings have direct duties towards animals,because animals are beings that can flourish, the flourishing ofanimals is intrinsically or inherently valuable, and that whichis conducive to their flourishing is a legitimate object of moralconcern. Looking for a tenable conception of direct dutiestowards animals, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations