Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Review of Ruth R. Faden and Tom L. Beauchamp: A History and Theory of Informed Consent[REVIEW]William G. Bartholome - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):605-606.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   419 citations  
  • Ending Concerns about Undue Inducement.Ezekiel J. Emanuel - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (1):100-105.
    For decades, worries about undue inducement have Pervaded clinical research, and are especially common when research is accompanied by payment or conducted in developing countries. Few ethical judgments carry as much moral opprobrium or are thought to undermine the ethical soundness of a clinical trial as thoroughly as undue inducement. Indeed, the admonition to prevent undue inducement is one of the few explicit instructions in the Common Rules requirements for informed consent.Despite their long history and pervasiveness, charges of undue inducement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Misunderstanding in Clinical Research: Distinguishing Therapeutic Misconception, Therapeutic Misestimation, & Therapeutic Optimism.Sam Horng & Christine Grady - 2003 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 25 (1):11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Public Health Ethics: Mapping the Terrain.James F. Childress, Ruth R. Faden, Ruth D. Gaare, Lawrence O. Gostin, Jeffrey Kahn, Richard J. Bonnie, Nancy E. Kass, Anna C. Mastroianni, Jonathan D. Moreno & Phillip Nieburg - 2002 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 30 (2):170-178.
    Public health ethics, like the field of public health it addresses, traditionally has focused more on practice and particular cases than on theory, with the result that some concepts, methods, and boundaries remain largely undefined. This paper attempts to provide a rough conceptual map of the terrain of public health ethics. We begin by briefly defining public health and identifying general features of the field that are particularly relevant for a discussion of public health ethics.Public health is primarily concerned with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • Ending Concerns About Undue Inducement.Ezekiel J. Emanuel - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (1):100-105.
    For decades, worries about undue inducement have Pervaded clinical research, and are especially common when research is accompanied by payment or conducted in developing countries. Few ethical judgments carry as much moral opprobrium or are thought to undermine the ethical soundness of a clinical trial as thoroughly as undue inducement. Indeed, the admonition to prevent undue inducement is one of the few explicit instructions in the Common Rules requirements for informed consent.Despite their long history and pervasiveness, charges of undue inducement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The influence of risk and monetary payment on the research participation decision making process.J. P. Bentley - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (3):293-298.
    Objectives: To determine the effects of risk and payment on subjects’ willingness to participate, and to examine how payment influences subjects’ potential behaviours and risk evaluations.Methods: A 3 × 3 , between subjects, completely randomised factorial design was used. Students enrolled at one of five US pharmacy schools read a recruitment notice and informed consent form for a hypothetical study, and completed a questionnaire. Risk level was manipulated using recruitment notices and informed consent documents from hypothetical biomedical research projects. Payment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The ethics and politics of human experimentation.Paul Murray McNeill - 1993 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book focuses on experimentation that is carried out on human beings, including medical research, drug research and research undertaken in the social sciences. It discusses the ethics of such experimentation and asks the question: who defends the interests of these human subjects and ensures that they are not harmed? The author finds that ethical research depends on the adequacy of review by committee. Indeed most countries now rely on research ethics committees for the protection of the interests of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Patient decision-making capacity and risk.Mark R. Wicclair - 1991 - Bioethics 5 (2):91–104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Rethinking research ethics.Rosamond Rhodes - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):7 – 28.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upoconcentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Exploitation in biomedical research.David B. Resnik - 2003 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24 (3):233--259.
    This essay analyzesexploitation in biomedical research in terms ofthree basic elements: harm, disrespect, orinjustice. There are also degrees ofexploitation, ranging from highly exploitationto minimally exploitation. Althoughexploitation is prima facie wrongful,some exploitative research studies are morallyjustified, all things considered. The reasonan exploitative study can still be ethical isthat other moral considerations, such as theautonomy of the research subject or the socialbenefits of research, may sometimes justifystudies that are minimally exploitative. Calling a research project exploitative doesnot end the debate about the merits (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • In defense of a regulated market in kidneys from living vendors.Benjamin E. Hippen - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (6):593 – 626.
    The current system of organ procurement which relies on donation is inadequate to the current and future need for transplantable kidneys. The growing disparity between demand and supply is accompanied by a steep human cost. I argue that a regulated market in organs from living vendors is the only plausible solution, and that objections common to opponents of organ markets are defeasible. I argue that a morally defensible market in kidneys from living vendors includes four characteristics: (1) the priority of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Money for research participation: Does it jeopardize informed consent?Christine Grady - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):40 – 44.
    Some are concerned about the possibility that offering money for research participation can constitute coercion or undue influence capable of distorting the judgment of potential research subjects and compromising the voluntariness of their informed consent. The author recognizes that more often than not there are multiple influences leading to decisions, including decisions about research participation. The concept of undue influence is explored, as well as the question of whether or not there is something uniquely distorting about money as opposed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Pharmaceutical research involving the homeless.Tom L. Beauchamp, Bruce Jennings, Eleanor D. Kinney & Robert J. Levine - 2002 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 27 (5):547 – 564.
    Discussions of research involving vulnerable populations have left the homeless comparatively ignored. Participation by these subjects in drug studies has the potential to be upsetting, inconvenient, or unpleasant. Participation occasionally produces injury, health emergencies, and chronic health problems. Nonetheless, no ethical justification exists for the categorical exclusion of homeless persons from research. The appropriate framework for informed consent for these subjects of pharmaceutical research is not a single event of oral or written consent, but a multi-staged arrangement of disclosure, dialogue, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Inducement, Due and Otherwise.Lisa Newton - 1982 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 4 (3):4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kidney for Sale by Owner.Mark J. Cherry - 2017 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 31 (2):171-187.
    This paper defends an in principle understanding of the authority of persons over themselves and, in consequence, argues for significant limits on morally permissible state authority. It also defends an account of the limits of permissible state action that distinguishes between the ability of persons to convey authority to common projects and what may be judged virtuous, good, safe, or proper to do. In terms of organ transplantation policy, it concludes that it is morally acceptable, and should be legally permissible, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Exploitation in the Use of Human Subjects for Medical Experimentation: A Re‐Examination of Basic Issues.Leonardo D. de Castro - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (3):259-268.
    Relatively subtle forms of exploitation of human subjects may arise from the inefficiency or incompetence of a researcher, from the existence of a power imbalance between principal and subject, or from the uneven distribution of research risks among various segments of the population. A powerful and knowledgeable person (or institution) may perpetrate the exploitation of an unempowered and ignorant individual even without intending to. There is an ethical burden on the former to protect the interests of the vulnerable. Excessive or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Patient Decision‐Making Capacity and Risk.Mark R. Wicclair - 1991 - Bioethics 5 (2):91-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Rethinking Research Ethics.Rosamond Rhodes - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (10):19-36.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upon concentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Stakes and Kidneys: Why Markets in Human Body Parts Are Morally Imperative.James Stacey Taylor - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (225):627-629.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • An ethical framework for the practice of paying research subjects.Terrence F. Ackerman - 1988 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 11 (4):1-4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Paying People to Participate in Research: Why not?McNeill Paul - 2002 - Bioethics 11 (5):390-396.
    This paper argues against paying people to participate in research. Volunteering to participate as a subject in a research program is not like taking a job. The main difference is to do with the risks inherent in research. Experimentation on human beings is, by definition, trying out something with an unknown consequence and exposes people to risks of harm which cannot be known in advance. This is the main reason for independent review by committee of research programs. It is based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Phase I cancer trials: A collusion of misunderstanding.Matthew Miller - 2000 - Hastings Center Report 30 (4):34-43.
    Physician‐investigators face the daunting task of enrolling desperate patients into Phase I cancer trials that are not meant to be therapeutic. Patients doggedly regard the trials as therapeutic, and researchers tend to collaborate in their confusion by glossing the trials’ true purposes and noting the occasional benefit that subjects accidentally receive. The disparity between hope and fact must be redressed by degrees, from many angles at once.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Bioethics: Private Choice and Common Good.Daniel Callahan - 1994 - Hastings Center Report 24 (3):28-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Medical Ethics in Ireland: A Decade of Change.Dolores Dooley - 1991 - Hastings Center Report 21 (1):18-21.
    As the ethical framework of the Catholic Church becomes incapable of accommodating the cultural diversity in Ireland, the search for a new moral discourse takes on a greater urgency. In its absence, litigation in Ireland is on the increase.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On paying money to research subjects: 'due' and 'undue' inducements.R. Macklin - 1981 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 3 (5):1-6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Undue Inducement: Nonsense on Stilts?Ezekiel J. Emanuel - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (5):9-13.
    1. The opinions expressed are the author's own. They do not reflect any position or policy of the National Institutes of Health, Public Health Service, Department of Health and Human Services, or any of the authors affiliated organizations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Justice and Healthcare: The Right to a Decent Minimum, Not Equality of Opportunity.Julian Savulescu - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):1a-3a.
    (2001). Justice and Healthcare: The Right to a Decent Minimum, Not Equality of Opportunity. The American Journal of Bioethics: Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 1a-3a.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Just Compensation: Paying Research Subjects Relative to the Risks They Bear.Jerry Menikoff - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):56-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Research Participation and Financial Inducements.David B. Resnik - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):54-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Payments to Participants: Beware of the Trojan Horses.Harold Y. Vanderpool - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):58-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Treating Research Subjects as Unskilled Wage Earners: A Risky Business.Nancy King Reame - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):53-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Fiction of "Undue Inducement": Why Researchers Should Be Allowed to Pay Participants Any Amount of Money for Any Reasonable Research Project.Julian Savulescu - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):1g-3g.
    (2001). The Fiction of 'Undue Inducement': Why Researchers Should Be Allowed to Pay Participants Any Amount of Money for Any Reasonable Research Project. The American Journal of Bioethics: Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 1g-3g.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Maybe We Should Pay Them More.Sheldon Zink - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):1h-1h.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Debate over Risk‐related Standards of Competence.Ian Wilks - 1997 - Bioethics 11 (5):413-426.
    This discussion paper continues the debate over risk‐related standards of mental competence which appears in Bioethics 5. Dan Brock there defends an approach to mental competence in patients which defines it as being relative to differing standards, more or less rigorous depending on the degree of risk involved in proposed treatments. But Mark Wicclair raises a problem for this approach: if significantly different levels of risk attach, respectively, to accepting and refusing the same treatment, then it is possible, on this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Inducement in Research.Martin Wilkinson & Andrew Moore - 1997 - Bioethics 11 (5):373-389.
    Opposition to inducement payments for research subjects is an international orthodoxy amongst writers of ethics committee guidelines. We offer an argument in favour of these payments. We also critically evaluate the best arguments we can find or devise against such payments, and except in one very limited range of circumstances, we find these unconvincing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Paying People to Participate in Research: Why not?Paul McNeill - 1997 - Bioethics 11 (5):390-396.
    This paper argues against paying people to participate in research. Volunteering to participate as a subject in a research program is not like taking a job. The main difference is to do with the risks inherent in research. Experimentation on human beings is, by definition, trying out something with an unknown consequence and exposes people to risks of harm which cannot be known in advance. This is the main reason for independent review by committee of research programs. It is based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Paying research subjects: participants' perspectives.M. L. Russell - 2000 - Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (2):126-130.
    Objective—To explore the opinions of unpaid healthy volunteers on the payment of research subjects.Design—Prospective cohort.Setting—Southern Alberta, Canada.Participants—Medically eligible persons responding to recruiting advertisements for a randomised vaccine trial were invited to take part in a study of informed consent at the point at which they formally consented or refused trial participation. Of 72 invited, 67 returned questionnaires at baseline and 54 at follow-up.Outcome measures—Proportions of persons who agreed or disagreed with three close-ended statements on the payment of research subjects; themes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Asymmetrical competence.Ian Wilks - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (2):154–159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The continuing debate over risk-related standards of competence.Mark R. Wicclair - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (2):149–153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Is informed consent enough? Monetary incentives for research participation and the integrity of biomedicine.Mark Kuczewski - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):49 – 51.
    (2001). Is Informed Consent Enough? Monetary Incentives for Research Participation and the Integrity of Biomedicine. The American Journal of Bioethics: Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 49-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Lay concepts in informed consent to biomedical research: The capacity to understand and appreciate risk.Ana Iltis - 2006 - Bioethics 20 (4):180–190.
    ABSTRACT Persons generally must give their informed consent to participate in research. To provide informed consent persons must be given information regarding the study in simple, lay language. Consent must be voluntary, and persons giving consent must be legally competent to consent and possess the capacity to understand and appreciate the information provided. This paper examines the relationship between the obligation to disclose information regarding risks and the requirement that persons have the capacity to understand and appreciate the information. There (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Exploitation in the use of human subjects for medical experimentation: A re-examination of basic issues.Leonardo D. de Castro - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (3):259–268.
    Relatively subtle forms of exploitation of human subjects may arise from the inefficiency or incompetence of a researcher, from the existence of a power imbalance between principal and subject, or from the uneven distribution of research risks among various segments of the population. A powerful and knowledgeable person (or institution) may perpetrate the exploitation of an unempowered and ignorant individual even without intending to. There is an ethical burden on the former to protect the interests of the vulnerable. Excessive or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Continuing the debate over risk-related standards of competence.Gita S. Cale - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (2):131–148.
    This discussion paper addresses Ian Wilks’ defence of the risk‐related standard of competence that appears in Bioethics 11. Wilks there argues that the puzzle posed by Mark Wicclair in Bioethics 5 against Dan Brock's argument in favour of a risk‐related standard of competence — namely that Brock’s argument allows for situations of asymmetrical competence — is not a genuine problem for a risk‐related standard of competence. To show this, Wilks presents what he believes to be two examples of real situations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Why Liberals Should Accept Financial Incentives for Organ Procurement.Robert M. Veatch - 2003 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (1):19-36.
    : Free-market libertarians have long supported incentives to increase organ procurement, but those oriented to justice traditionally have opposed them. This paper presents the reasons why those worried about justice should reconsider financial incentives and tolerate them as a lesser moral evil. After considering concerns about discrimination and coercion and setting them aside, it is suggested that the real moral concern should be manipulation of the neediest. The one offering the incentive (the government) has the resources to eliminate the basic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Conscription of Cadaveric Organs for Transplantation: Neglected Again.Aaron Spital - 2003 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (2):169-174.
    : The March 2003 issue of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal was devoted to cadaveric organ procurement. All the discussed proposals for solving the severe organ shortage place a higher value on respecting individual and/or family autonomy than on maximizing recovery of organs. Because of this emphasis on autonomy and historically high refusal rates, I believe that none of the proposals is likely to achieve the goal of ensuring an adequate supply of transplantable organs. An alternative approach, conscription of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations