Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Ethics without principles.Jonathan Dancy - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this much-anticipated book, Jonathan Dancy offers the only available full-scale treatment of particularism in ethics, a view with which he has been associated for twenty years. Dancy now presents particularism as the view that the possibility of moral thought and judgement does not in any way depend on an adequate supply of principles. He grounds this claim on a form of reasons-holism, holding that what is a reason in one case need not be any reason in another, and maintaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   673 citations  
  • Absorption and Theatricality: Painting and Beholder in the Age of Diderot.Michael Fried - 1980 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (2):200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Moralistic Fallacy: On the 'Appropriateness' of Emotions.Justin D'Arms & Daniel Jacobson - 2000 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):65-90.
    Philosophers often call emotions appropriate or inappropriate. What is meant by such talk? In one sense, explicated in this paper, to call an emotion appropriate is to say that the emotion is fitting: it accurately presents its object as having certain evaluative features. For instance, envy might be thought appropriate when one's rival has something good which one lacks. But someone might grant that a circumstance has these features, yet deny that envy is appropriate, on the grounds that it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   303 citations  
  • The ethical criticism of art.Berys Gaut - 1998 - In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 182--203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • The Moralistic Fallacy.Daniel Jacobson - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):65-90.
    Philosophers often call emotions appropriate or inappropriate. What is meant by such talk? In one sense, explicated in this paper, to call an emotion appropriate is to say that the emotion is fitting: it accurately presents its object as having certain evaluative features. For instance, envy might be thought appropriate when one’s rival has something good which one lacks. But someone might grant that a circumstance has these features, yet deny that envy is appropriate, on the grounds that it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   313 citations  
  • The problem of non-perceptual art.James Shelley - 2003 - British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (4):363-378.
    Consider the following three propositions: (R) Artworks necessarily have aesthetic properties that are relevant to their appreciation as artworks. (S) Aesthetic properties necessarily depend, at least in part, on properties perceived by means of the five senses. (X) There exist artworks that need not be perceived by means of the five senses to be appreciated as artworks. The independent plausibility and apparent joint inconsistency of these three propositions give rise to what I refer to as ‘the problem of non-perceptual art’. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Aesthetics of Architecture.Roger Scruton - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (214):567-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Music's moral character.María José Alcaraz León - 2012 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 31 (3):179-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Defending Particularism.Jonathan Dancy - 1999 - Metaphilosophy 30 (1&2):25-32.
    In this brief response I argue that Sinnott‐Armstrong has underestimated the complexities that moral principles will have to circumvent if they are to survive particularist criticism. I also argue that we cannot yet accept Gert's accounts of moral relevance and of how a sound moral rule can survive exceptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures edited by lopes, dominic mciver.Mark Rollins - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (4):479-481.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The puzzle of mimesis.Dominic McIver Lopes - 2005 - In Dominic Lopes (ed.), Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Pictures enable us to see scenes in marked surfaces. This raises a puzzle—how can an evaluation of a picture as a vehicle for seeing-in differ from an evaluation of the scene itself? To solve the puzzle, we must understand the variety of ways seeing-in relates to seeing a marked surface.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What are the Options?Jonathan Dancy - 2004 - In Ethics without principles. New York: Oxford University Press.
    An introductory chapter that maps the possible views about the relation between moral thought and moral principles, showing how extreme the particularist position is. Particularism is contrasted with Rossian intuitionism and its use of prima facie principles; and the particularist account of moral reasoning is contrasted with non-monotonic theories, and with the views of Kagan and Scanlon.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations