Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Moral Principles and Political Obligations.A. John Simmons - 1979 - Princeton University Press.
    Every political theorist will need this book . . . . It is more 'important' than 90% of the work published in philosophy."--Joel Feinberg, University of Arizona.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Bad Samaritan Laws: Harm, Help, or Hype?Heid M. Malm - 2000 - Law and Philosophy 19 (6):707 - 750.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • In harm's way: AMA physicians and the duty to treat.Chalmers C. Clark - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (1):65 – 87.
    In June 2001, the American Medical Association (AMA) issued a revised and expanded version of the Principles of Medical Ethics (last published in 1980). In light of the new and more comprehensive document, the present essay is geared to consideration of a longstanding tension between physician's autonomy rights and societal obligations in the AMA Code. In particular, it will be argued that a duty to treat overrides AMA autonomy rights in social emergencies, even in cases that involve personal risk to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Physician Obligation in Disaster Preparedness and Response.Karine Morin, Daniel Higginson & Michael Goldrich - 2006 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (4):417-421.
    The terrorist attacks of 2001 were a reminder that individual and collective safety cannot be taken for granted. Since then, physicians, alongside public health professionals and other healthcare professionals as well as nonhealthcare personnel, have been developing plans to enhance the protection of public health and the provision of medical care in response to various threats, including acts of terrorism or bioterrorism. Included in those plans are strategies to attend to large numbers of victims and help prevent greater harm to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Commentary: Physicians as public servants in the setting of bioterrorism.G. Caleb Alexander & John D. Lantos - 2006 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (4):422-423.
    Physicians have special professional obligations to respond to medical emergencies. A bioterrorism attack would be a medical emergency. Thus, it seems that physicians would have an obligation to respond to a bioterrorist attack. However, the scope of those obligations, and their limits, are vexed topics. General rules may be comforting but the details and nuances of particular situations will always be relevant.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Commentary: Physicians as Public Servants in the Setting of Bioterrorism.G. Caleb Alexander & John D. Lantos - 2006 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (4):422-423.
    Physicians have special professional obligations to respond to medical emergencies. A bioterrorism attack would be a medical emergency. Thus, it seems that physicians would have an obligation to respond to a bioterrorist attack. However, the scope of those obligations, and their limits, are vexed topics. General rules may be comforting but the details and nuances of particular situations will always be relevant.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Commentary: The Professional Obligation of Physicians in Times of Hazard and Need.Rosamond Rhodes - 2006 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (4):424-428.
    Those who read only the introductory section of “Physician Obligation in Disaster Preparedness and Response,” the statement from the AMA's Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, apparently an elaboration on CEJA Opinion 3-I-04, E-9.067, will find an expression of laudable professional responsibility in the face of a disaster. There the AMA authors explicitly acknowledge “that unique responsibilities beyond planning rest on the shoulders of the medical profession”. They also declare that, “physicians are needed to care for victims. In some instances, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is It Rape?: On Acquaintance Rape and Taking Women’s Consent Seriously.Joan McGregor - 2005 - Routledge.
    The issue of acquaintance rape has been gaining increased prominence in recent years. In this book Joan McGregor analyses the ethical and legal problems that arise in connection with acquaintance rape cases. She discusses with great clarity and precision the complexities involved in notions such as consent, force, autonomy, power, intention and the impairment of responsibility through drugs, alcohol and mental illness. Arguing that criminal rape laws are too narrow, capturing only cases where there is clearly recognized physical violence and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Moral Principles and Political Obligations.A. John Simmons - 1979 - Princeton University Press.
    Outlining the major competing theories in the history of political and moral philosophy--from Locke and Hume through Hart, Rawls, and Nozick--John Simmons attempts to understand and solve the ancient problem of political obligation. Under what conditions and for what reasons, he asks, are we morally bound to obey the law and support the political institutions of our countries?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • The American medical ethics revolution: how the AMA's code of ethics has transformed physicians' relationships to patients, professionals, and society.Robert Baker (ed.) - 1999 - Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    The American Medical Association enacted its Code of Ethics in 1847, the first such national codification. In this volume, a distinguished group of experts from the fields of medicine, bioethics, and history of medicine reflect on the development of medical ethics in the United States, using historical analyses as a springboard for discussions of the problems of the present, including what the editors call "a sense of moral crisis precipitated by the shift from a system of fee-for-service medicine to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Diminishing returns? Risk and the duty to care in the Sars epidemic.Lynette Reid - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (4):348–361.
    The seriousness of the risk that healthcare workers faced during SARS, and their response of service in the face of this risk, brings to light unrealistic assumptions about duty and risk that informed the debate on duty to care in the early years of HIV/AIDS. Duty to care is not based upon particular virtues of the health professions, but arises from social reflection on what response to an epidemic would be consistent with our values and our needs, recognizing our shared (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Killing, letting die, and simple conflicts.H. M. Malm - 1989 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (3):238-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • When pestilence prevails physician responsibilities in epidemics.Samuel J. Huber & Matthew K. Wynia - 2004 - American Journal of Bioethics 4 (1):5 – 11.
    The threat of bioterrorism, the emergence of the SARS epidemic, and a recent focus on professionalism among physicians, present a timely opportunity for a review of, and renewed commitment to, physician obligations to care for patients during epidemics. The professional obligation to care for contagious patients is part of a larger "duty to treat," which historically became accepted when 1) a risk of nosocomial infection was perceived, 2) an organized professional body existed to promote the duty, and 3) the public (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • How infectious diseases got left out – and what this omission might have meant for bioethics.Leslie P. Francis, Margaret P. Battin, Jay A. Jacobson, Charles B. Smith & And Jeffrey Botkin - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (4):307–322.
    ABSTRACT In this article, we first document the virtually complete absence of infectious disease examples and concerns at the time bioethics emerged as a field. We then argue that this oversight was not benign by considering two central issues in the field, informed consent and distributive justice, and showing how they might have been framed differently had infectiousness been at the forefront of concern. The solution to this omission might be to apply standard approaches in liberal bioethics, such as autonomy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Ontological Status of Consent and its Implications for the Law on Rape.H. M. Malm - 1996 - Legal Theory 2 (2):147-164.
    One of the dominant themes of the symposium from which this collection of articles arose was the ontological status of consent. Is consent a particular state of mind? Is it the signification of that state of mind via a conventionally recognized act? Or, is consent a normative concept that evaluates not only the presence of a state of mind or act, but also the appropriateness of that state of mind or act in the particular circumstances?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On pandemics and the duty to care: whose duty? who cares? [REVIEW]Carly Ruderman, C. Tracy, Cécile Bensimon, Mark Bernstein, Laura Hawryluck, Randi Zlotnik Shaul & Ross Upshur - 2006 - BMC Medical Ethics 7 (1):1-6.
    Background As a number of commentators have noted, SARS exposed the vulnerabilities of our health care systems and governance structures. Health care professionals (HCPs) and hospital systems that bore the brunt of the SARS outbreak continue to struggle with the aftermath of the crisis. Indeed, HCPs – both in clinical care and in public health – were severely tested by SARS. Unprecedented demands were placed on their skills and expertise, and their personal commitment to their profession was severely tried. Many (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Moral Principles and Political Obligations.A. John Simmons - 1980 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 87 (4):568-568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • On pandemics and the duty to care: whose duty? who cares?Carly Ruderman, C. Shawn Tracy, Cécile M. Bensimon, Mark Bernstein, Laura Hawryluck, Randi Z. Shaul & Ross E. G. Upshur - 2006 - BMC Medical Ethics 7 (1):5.
    BackgroundAs a number of commentators have noted, SARS exposed the vulnerabilities of our health care systems and governance structures. Health care professionals (HCPs) and hospital systems that bore the brunt of the SARS outbreak continue to struggle with the aftermath of the crisis. Indeed, HCPs – both in clinical care and in public health – were severely tested by SARS. Unprecedented demands were placed on their skills and expertise, and their personal commitment to their profession was severely tried. Many were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Profession and professional ethics.David T. Ozar - 1995 - Encyclopedia of Bioethics 4:2103-2112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Moral Principles and Political Obligations.Diana T. Meyers - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (3):472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • The Fragile Web of Responsibility: AIDS and the Duty to neat.John D. Arras - 1988 - Hastings Center Report 18 (2):10-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Is It Rape? On Acquaintance Rape and Taking Women's Consent Seriously.Joan Mcgregor - 2006 - Law and Philosophy 25 (6):663-672.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • How Infectious Diseases Got Left Out – and What This Omission Might Have Meant for Bioethics.Leslie P. Francis, Margaret P. Battin, Jay A. Jacobson, Charles B. Smith & Jeffrey Botkin - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (4):307-322.
    ABSTRACT In this article, we first document the virtually complete absence of infectious disease examples and concerns at the time bioethics emerged as a field. We then argue that this oversight was not benign by considering two central issues in the field, informed consent and distributive justice, and showing how they might have been framed differently had infectiousness been at the forefront of concern. The solution to this omission might be to apply standard approaches in liberal bioethics, such as autonomy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Politics of Physicians' Responsibility in Epidemics: A Note on History.Daniel M. Fox - 1988 - Hastings Center Report 18 (2):5-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Duty to Treat or Right to Refuse?Norman Daniels - 1991 - Hastings Center Report 21 (2):36-46.
    By entering the medical profession, physicians have consented to accept a standard level of risk of infection. In most instances, the risk of contracting HIV does not exceed this level.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Sars As An Ethical Test.James Dwyer - 2003 - Eubios Journal of Asian and International Bioethics 13 (4):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation