Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Scientific pluralism reconsidered: a new approach to the (dis)unity of science.Stéphanie Ruphy - 2016 - Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
    Can we expect our scientific theories to make up a unified structure, or do they form a kind of “patchwork” whose pieces remain independent from each other? Does the proliferation of sometimes-incompatible representations of the same phenomenon compromise the ability of science to deliver reliable knowledge? Is there a single correct way to classify things that science should try to discover, or is taxonomic pluralism here to stay? These questions are at the heart of philosophical debate on the unity or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Theory of Probability.Harold Jeffreys - 1939 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Another title in the reissued Oxford Classic Texts in the Physical Sciences series, Jeffrey's Theory of Probability, first published in 1939, was the first to develop a fundamental theory of scientific inference based on the ideas of Bayesian statistics. His ideas were way ahead of their time and it is only in the past ten years that the subject of Bayes' factors has been significantly developed and extended. Until recently the two schools of statistics were distinctly different and set apart. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Philosophy of Cosmology.Chris Smeenk - 2013 - In Robert W. Batterman (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 607-652.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Can We Justifiably Assume the Cosmological Principle in Order to Break Model Underdetermination in Cosmology?Claus Beisbart - 2009 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 40 (2):175-205.
    If cosmology is to obtain knowledge about the whole universe, it faces an underdetermination problem: Alternative space-time models are compatible with our evidence. The problem can be avoided though, if there are good reasons to adopt the Cosmological Principle (CP), because, assuming the principle, one can confine oneself to the small class of homogeneous and isotropic space-time models. The aim of this paper is to ask whether there are good reasons to adopt the Cosmological Principle in order to avoid underdetermination (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Bayesian Who Knew Too Much.Yann Benétreau-Dupin - 2015 - Synthese 192 (5):1527-1542.
    In several papers, John Norton has argued that Bayesianism cannot handle ignorance adequately due to its inability to distinguish between neutral and disconfirming evidence. He argued that this inability sows confusion in, e.g., anthropic reasoning in cosmology or the Doomsday argument, by allowing one to draw unwarranted conclusions from a lack of knowledge. Norton has suggested criteria for a candidate for representation of neutral support. Imprecise credences (families of credal probability functions) constitute a Bayesian-friendly framework that allows us to avoid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Who Should Be Afraid of the Jeffreys-Lindley Paradox?Aris Spanos - 2013 - Philosophy of Science 80 (1):73-93.
    The article revisits the large n problem as it relates to the Jeffreys-Lindley paradox to compare the frequentist, Bayesian, and likelihoodist approaches to inference and evidence. It is argued that what is fallacious is to interpret a rejection of as providing the same evidence for a particular alternative, irrespective of n; this is an example of the fallacy of rejection. Moreover, the Bayesian and likelihoodist approaches are shown to be susceptible to the fallacy of acceptance. The key difference is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Method-Driven Experiments and the Search for Dark Matter.Siska De Baerdemaeker - 2021 - Philosophy of Science 88 (1):124-144.
    Since the discovery of dark matter in the 1980s, multiple experiments have been set up to detect dark matter particles through some other mode than gravity. Particle physicists provide detailed jus...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Simplicity and Simplification in Astrophysical Modeling.Sibylle Anderl - 2018 - Philosophy of Science 85 (5):819-831.
    With the ever-growing quality of observational data in astronomy, the complexity of astrophysical models has been increasing in turn. This trend raises the question: Are there still reasons to prefer simpler models if the final goal is an actual model-target comparison? I argue for two aspects in which astrophysical research may favor models having reduced complexity: first, to address the problem of determining the values of adjustable parameters and, second, to pave the way for a validation of the model based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A statistical paradox.D. V. Lindley - 1957 - Biometrika 44 (1/2):187-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Theory of Probability.Harold Jeffreys - 1940 - Philosophy of Science 7 (2):263-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   244 citations