Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A cognitive theory of pretense.Stephen P. Stich & Shaun Nichols - 2000 - Cognition 74 (2):115-147.
    Recent accounts of pretense have been underdescribed in a number of ways. In this paper, we present a much more explicit cognitive account of pretense. We begin by describing a number of real examples of pretense in children and adults. These examples bring out several features of pretense that any adequate theory of pretense must accommodate, and we use these features to develop our theory of pretense. On our theory, pretense representations are contained in a separate mental workspace, a Possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Imagining and believing: The promise of a single code.Shaun Nichols - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2):129-39.
    Recent cognitive accounts of the imagination propose that imagining and believing are in the same “code”. According to the single code hypothesis, cognitive mechanisms that can take input from both imagining and from believing will process imagination-based inputs (“pretense representations”) and isomorphic beliefs in much the same way. In this paper, I argue that the single code hypothesis provides a unified and independently motivated explanation for a wide range of puzzles surrounding fiction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • On the relation between pretense and belief.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2003 - In Matthew Kieran & Dominic McIver Lopes (eds.), Imagination, Philosophy and the Arts. New York: Routledge. pp. 125--141.
    By the age of two, children are able to engage in highly elaborate games of symbolic pretense, in which objects and actions in the actual world are taken to stand for objects and actions in a realm of make-believe. These games of pretense are marked by the presence of two central features, which I will call quarantining and mirroring (see also Leslie 1987; Perner 1991). Quarantining is manifest to the extent that events within the pretense-episode are taken to have effects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Really believing in fiction.David B. Suits - 2006 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (3):369–386.
    How is it possible to respond emotionally to that which we believe is not the case? All of the many responses to this "paradox of fiction" make one or more of three important mistakes: (1) neglecting the context of believing, (2) assuming that belief is an all-or-nothing affair, and (3) assuming that if you believe that p then you cannot also reasonably believe that not-p. My thesis is that we react emotionally to stories because we do believe what stories tell (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Philosophical Adventures with Children.Michael S. Pritchard - 1985
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Exploring the Imagination to Establish Frameworks for Learning.Gregory Heath - 2008 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 27 (2):115-123.
    This paper continues to explore the relationship between the imagination and learning. It has been claimed by Maxine Greene, amongst others, that imagination is the most important of the cognitive capacities for learning; the reason being that ‘it permits us to give credence to alternative realities’. However little work has been done on what constitutes this capacity for the imagination. This paper draws on Husserl and Wittgenstein to frame a model of imagination that derives from the perspective of the ‘transcendental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Other Half of the Child.Kieran Egan - 1987 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 7 (1):2-5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paternalism and the Rationality of the Child.Rosalind Ekman Ladd - 1985 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 6 (1):15-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation