Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Einstein's controversy with Drude and the origin of statistical mechanics: A new glimpse from the “Love Letters”.Jürgen Renn - 1997 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 51 (4):315-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Paul Ehrenfest on the Necessity of Quanta (1911): Discontinuity, Quantization, Corpuscularity, and Adiabatic Invariance.Enric Pérez & Luis Navarro - 2004 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 58 (2):97-141.
    Our object in this paper is to study the antecedents, contents, implications, and impact of a not well-known or appreciated paper by EHRENFEST in 1911 on the essential nature of the different quantum hypotheses in radiation theory. After a careful analysis of EHRENFEST’s notebooks, correspondence, and publications, we conclude that the essential points of EHRENFEST’s paper were not perceived to a large extent, and hence that its implications were not considered thoroughly. Specifically, we show that EHRENFEST contributed significantly to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • ‘Language, Truth and Reason’ 30years later.Ian Hacking - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (4):599-609.
    This paper traces the origins of the styles project, originally presented as ‘styles of scientific reasoning’. ‘Styles of scientific thinking & doing’ is a better label; the styles can also be called genres, or, ways of finding out. A. C. Crombie’s template of six fundamentally distinct ones was turned into a philosophical tool, but with a tinge of Paul Feyerabend’s anarchism. Ways of finding out are not defined by necessary and sufficient conditions, but can be recognized as distinct within a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • ‘Style’ for historians and philosophers.Ian Hacking - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 23 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Compendium of the foundations of classical statistical physics.Jos Uffink - 2006 - In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of physics. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Roughly speaking, classical statistical physics is the branch of theoretical physics that aims to account for the thermal behaviour of macroscopic bodies in terms of a classical mechanical model of their microscopic constituents, with the help of probabilistic assumptions. In the last century and a half, a fair number of approaches have been developed to meet this aim. This study of their foundations assesses their coherence and analyzes the motivations for their basic assumptions, and the interpretations of their central concepts. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • The Creative Power of Formal Analogies in Physics: The Case of Albert Einstein.Yves Gingras - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (5-6):529-541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Atoms, Entropy, Quanta: Einstein’s Miraculous Argument of 1905.John D. Norton - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37 (1):71-100.
    In the sixth section of his light quantum paper of 1905, Einstein presented the miraculous argument, as I shall call it. Pointing out an analogy with ideal gases and dilute solutions, he showed that the macroscopic, thermodynamic properties of high-frequency heat radiation carry a distinctive signature of finitely many, spatially localized, independent components and so inferred that it consists of quanta. I describe how Einstein's other statistical papers of 1905 had already developed and exploited the idea that the ideal gas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Layered history: Styles of reasoning as stratified conditions of possibility.James Elwick - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (4):619-627.
    This paper depicts Ian Hacking’s ‘styles of reasoning’ as conditions of possibility. After distinguishing between possibilities and causes, it articulates the implicit stratigraphical metaphor used to describe the relationship between different conditions of possibility, with ‘lower’ layers being necessary for ‘higher’ ones. It notes the use of this stratigraphical metaphor in the work of multiple scholars in history and in science studies. The paper suggests three ways in which this model can be useful: clarifying the definition and use of ‘context’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Atoms, entropy, quanta: Einstein's miraculous argument of 1905.John D. Norton - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37 (1):71-100.
    In the sixth section of his light quantum paper of 1905, Einstein presented the miraculous argument, as I shall call it. Pointing out an analogy with ideal gases and dilute solutions, he showed that the macroscopic, thermodynamic properties of high frequency heat radiation carry a distinctive signature of finitely many, spatially localized, independent components and so inferred that it consists of quanta. I describe how Einstein’s other statistical papers of 1905 had already developed and exploited the idea that the ideal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Trajectories in the History and Historiography of Physics in the Twentieth Century.Richard Staley - 2013 - History of Science 51 (2):151-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Odd Couple: Boltzmann, Planck and the Application of Statistics to Physics (1900-1913).Massimiliano Badino - 2009 - Annalen Der Physik 18 (2-3):81-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Gibbs, Einstein and the Foundations of Statistical Mechanics.Luis Navarro - 1998 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 53 (2):147-180.
    It is generally accepted that, around the turn of the century, GIBBS and EINSTEIN independently developed two equivalent formulations of statistical mechanics. GIBBS version is taken as genuine and rigorous, while EINSTEINs, despite some features which are characteristic of him, is usually considered a not totally satisfactory attempt.It will be shown in the present work that such a picture is oversimplified and requires further nuancing. In fact, there are significant differences, with important implications which have not been sufficiently examined, between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Einstein’s quantum theory of the monatomic ideal gas: non-statistical arguments for a new statistics.Tilman Sauer & Enric Pérez - 2010 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 64 (5):561-612.
    In this article, we analyze the third of three papers, in which Einstein presented his quantum theory of the ideal gas of 1924–1925. Although it failed to attract the attention of Einstein’s contemporaries and although also today very few commentators refer to it, we argue for its significance in the context of Einstein’s quantum researches. It contains an attempt to extend and exhaust the characterization of the monatomic ideal gas without appealing to combinatorics. Its ambiguities illustrate Einstein’s confusion with his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fritz London and the scale of quantum mechanisms.Daniela Monaldi - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 60:35-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The classical roots of wave mechanics: Schrödinger's transformations of the optical-mechanical analogy.Christian Joas & Christoph Lehner - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 (4):338-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Feynman’s War: Modelling Weapons, Modelling Nature.Peter Galison - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 29 (3):391-434.
    This article examines the forces that have made federal scientific publication an essentially private enterprise. Particular attention is paid to the rise of the scientific community in the American political system. The period under review begins roughly with 1941 and American involvement in World War II, which coincides with the establishment of the Office of Scientific Research and Development (ORSD). The article examines OSRD's method of conducting federal scientific research, its contractual system, and the new publishing paradigm that it engendered. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A note on the prehistory of indistinguishable particles.Daniela Monaldi - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 (4):383-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Creative Power of Formal Analogies in Physics: The Case of Albert Einstein.Ricardo Karam - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (5-6):529-541.
    In order to show how formal analogies between different physical systems play an important conceptual work in physics, this paper analyzes the evolution of Einstein’s thoughts on the structure of radiation from the point of view of the formal analogies he used as “lenses” to “see” through the “black box” of Planck’s blackbody radiation law. A comparison is also made with his 1925 paper on the quantum gas where he used the same formal methods. Changes of formal points of view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Editorial.[author unknown] - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 29 (3):287-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Fin de Siècle Thesis.Richard Staley - 2008 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 31 (4):311-330.
    Die Fin de Siècle‐These. Der Aufsatz untersucht das Verhältnis zwischen John Heilbrons Argumentation, die Physiker des ‘fin de siecle’ hätten Bild und Substanz ihrer Disziplin kulturellen Belangen angepasst, und Paul Formans Interpretation der Akausalität in der Weimarer Periode. Ergänzend zu ihrer Fokussierung auf Repräsentationen anstelle von Wahrheit, legten die von Heilbron benannten Anhänger “deskriptionistischer” Epistemologien den Schwerpunkt auf Methodik, statistische anstelle kausaler Erklärungen, historisches Verständnis von Epistemologie und unterstrichen die Beziehungen zwischen der Physik und anderen Disziplinen. Ihre Perspektive liefert einen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Louis de Broglie and Bose-Einstein Statistics.Agostino Desalvo - 1986 - Epistemologia 9 (2):359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Insuperable difficulties: Einstein's statistical road to molecular physics.Jos Uffink - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37 (1):36-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Vienna indeterminism: Mach, Boltzmann, exner.Michael Stöltzner - 1999 - Synthese 119 (1-2):85-111.
    The present paper studies a specific way of addressing the question whether the laws involving the basic constituents of nature are statistical. While most German physicists, above all Planck, treated the issues of determinism and causality within a Kantian framework, the tradition which I call Vienna Indeterminism began from Mach’s reinterpretation of causality as functional dependence. This severed the bond between causality and realism because one could no longer avail oneself of a priori categories as a criterion for empirical reality. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations