Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Fitting Attitudes, Finkish Goods, and Value Appearances.Graham Oddie - 2016 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 11.
    According to Fitting Attitude theorists, for something to possess a certain value it is necessary and sufficient that it be fitting to take a certain attitude to the bearer of that value. This seems obvious for thick evaluative attributes, but less obvious for thin evaluative attributes. This chapter argues that the fitting response to the thin evaluative attributes of states is desire. The good is what it is fitting to desire, the bad what it is fitting to be averse to, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ethics, Inventing Right and Wrong.[author unknown] - 1977 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 43 (3):581-582.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Likeness to Truth.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):296-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The autonomy of ethics.Arthur Prior - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3):199–206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • The Logic of Questions and Answers by N. D. Belnap and T. B. Steel. [REVIEW]Martin Bell - 1979 - Mind 88 (350):297-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)Hume on Is and Ought.Charles Pigden - 2011 - Philosophy Now 83:18-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong.Fred Feldman & J. L. Mackie - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (1):134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   676 citations  
  • The Fictionalist’s Attitude Problem.Graham Oddie & Daniel Demetriou - 2007 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (5):485-498.
    According to John Mackie, moral talk is representational but its metaphysical presuppositions are wildly implausible. This is the basis of Mackie's now famous error theory: that moral judgments are cognitively meaningful but systematically false. Of course, Mackie went on to recommend various substantive moral judgments, and, in the light of his error theory, that has seemed odd to a lot of folk. Richard Joyce has argued that Mackie's approach can be vindicated by a fictionalist account of moral discourse. And Mark (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)A refutation of morals.John Mackie - 1946 - Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 24 (1-2):77-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Likeness to Truth.Graham Oddie - 1986 - Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel.
    What does it take for one proposition to be closer to the truth than another. In this, the first published monograph on the topic, Oddie develops a comprehensive theory that takes the likeness in truthlikeness seriously.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • (1 other version)Fitting attitudes, finkish goods, and value appearances.Graham Oddie - 2010 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 74-101.
    According to Fitting Attitude theorists, for something to possess a certain value it is necessary and sufficient that it be fitting (appropriate, or good, or obligatory, or something) to take a certain attitude to the bearer of that value. The idea seems obvious for thick evaluative attributes, but less obvious for the thin evaluative attributes—like goodness, betterness, and degrees of value. This paper is an extended argument for the thesis that the fitting response to the thin evaluative attributes of states (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Barriers to implication.Greg Restall - 2010 - In Charles Pigden (ed.), Hume and ‘is’ and ‘ought’: new essays. Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Implication barrier theses deny that one can derive sentences of one type from sentences of another. Hume’s Law is an implication barrier thesis; it denies that one can derive an ‘ought’ (a normative sentence) from an ‘is’ (a descriptive sentence). Though Hume’s Law is controversial, some barrier theses are philosophical platitudes; in his Lectures on Logical Atomism, Bertrand Russell claims: You can never arrive at a general proposition by inference particular propositions alone. You will always have to have at least (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Statements partly about observation.David Lewis - 1988 - Philosophical Papers 17 (1):1-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Hume on Is and Ought.Charles Pigden (ed.) - 2010 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    It ‘seems altogether inconceivable', says Hume, that this ‘new relation' ought ‘can be a deduction' from others ‘which are entirely different from it' The idea that you can't derive an Ought from an Is, moral conclusions from non-moral premises, has proved enormously influential. But what did Hume mean by this famous dictum? Was he correct? How does it fit in with the rest of his philosophy? And what does this suggest about the nature of moral judgements? This collection, the first (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Value, reality, and desire.Graham Oddie - 2005 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    Value, Reality, and Desire is an extended argument for a robust realism about value. The robust realist affirms the following distinctive theses. There are genuine claims about value which are true or false--there are facts about value. These value-facts are mind-independent - they are not reducible to desires or other mental states, or indeed to any non-mental facts of a non-evaluative kind. And these genuine, mind-independent, irreducible value-facts are causally efficacious. Values, quite literally, affect us. These are not particularly fashionable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Is it Always Fallacious to Derive Values From Facts?Mark T. Nelson - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (4):553-562.
    Charles Pigden has argued for a logical Is/Ought gap on the grounds of the conservativeness of logic. I offer a counter-example which shows that Pigden’s argument is unsound and that there need be no logical gap between Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion. My counter-example is an argument which is logically valid, has only Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion, does not purport to violate the conservativeness of logic, and does not rely on controversial assumptions about Aristotelian biology or 'institutional facts.'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Minding the Is-Ought Gap.Campbell Brown - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (1):53-69.
    The ‘No Ought From Is’ principle (or ‘NOFI’) states that a valid argument cannot have both an ethical conclusion and non-ethical premises. Arthur Prior proposed several well-known counterexamples, including the following: Tea-drinking is common in England; therefore, either tea-drinking is common in England or all New Zealanders ought to be shot. My aim in this paper is to defend NOFI against Prior’s counterexamples. I propose two novel interpretations of NOFI and prove that both are true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)A refutation of morals.John Mackie - 1946 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 24 (1-2):77 – 90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The logic of questions and answers.Nuel D. Belnap & Thomas B. Steel (eds.) - 1976 - New Haven/London: Yale University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong.John Leslie Mackie - 1977 - New York: Penguin Books.
    John Mackie's stimulating book is a complete and clear treatise on moral theory. His writings on normative ethics-the moral principles he recommends-offer a fresh approach on a much neglected subject, and the work as a whole is undoubtedly a major contribution to modern philosophy.The author deals first with the status of ethics, arguing that there are not objective values, that morality cannot be discovered but must be made. He examines next the content of ethics, seeing morality as a functional device, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1170 citations  
  • The Foundations of Frege’s Logic.Pavel Tichý - 1988 - New York: de Gruyter.
    Chapter One: Constructions. Entities, constructions, and functions When one travels from Los Angeles to New York, going, say, by way of St. Louis, Chicago, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Constructions.Pavel Tichy - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (4):514-534.
    The paper deals with the semantics of mathematical notation. In arithmetic, for example, the syntactic shape of a formula represents a particular way of specifying, arriving at, or constructing an arithmetical object (that is, a number, a function, or a truth value). A general definition of this sense of "construction" is proposed and compared with related notions, in particular with Frege's concept of "function" and Carnap's concept of "intensional isomorphism." It is argued that constructions constitute the proper subject matter of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)Barriers to Implication.Gillian Russell & Greg Restall - 2010 - In Charles Pigden (ed.), Hume on Is and Ought. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    The formulation and proof of Hume’s Law and several related inference barrier theses.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The autonomy of ethics.A. N. Prior - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3):199 – 206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Logic and the autonomy of ethics.Charles R. Pigden - 1989 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67 (2):127 – 151.
    My first paper on the Is/Ought issue. The young Arthur Prior endorsed the Autonomy of Ethics, in the form of Hume’s No-Ought-From-Is (NOFI) but the later Prior developed a seemingly devastating counter-argument. I defend Prior's earlier logical thesis (albeit in a modified form) against his later self. However it is important to distinguish between three versions of the Autonomy of Ethics: Ontological, Semantic and Ontological. Ontological Autonomy is the thesis that moral judgments, to be true, must answer to a realm (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Cognitivism, a priori deduction, and Moore.Frank Jackson - 2003 - Ethics 113 (3):557-575.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Foundations of Frege's Logic.Gregor K. Frey - 1993 - Noûs 27 (4):532-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Value, judgement, and desire: Bridging the gaps.Graham Oddie - 2005 - In Value, reality, and desire. New York: Clarendon Press.
    This chapter presents a different and complementary take on the nature of realism and antirealism, one which has a clearer application to value when our journey is almost over than it would have here just as we embark. It argues that realism can be characterized as the affirmation of three important logical gaps. First, there is the gap between appearance and reality — the logical gap which constitutes the possibility of illusion or distortion. Second, there is the gap between reality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations