Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A second-person neuroscience in interaction.Leonhard Schilbach, Bert Timmermans, Vasudevi Reddy, Alan Costall, Gary Bente, Tobias Schlicht & Kai Vogeley - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (4):441-462.
    In this response we address additions to as well as criticisms and possible misinterpretations of our proposal for a second-person neuroscience. We map out the most crucial aspects of our approach by (1) acknowledging that second-person engaged interaction is not the only way to understand others, although we claim that it is ontogenetically prior; (2) claiming that spectatorial paradigms need to be complemented in order to enable a full understanding of social interactions; and (3) restating that our theoretical proposal not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Perception: A Representative Theory by Frank Jackson. [REVIEW]David M. Rosenthal - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (1):28-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Perception: A Representative Theory.Stephanie A. Ross - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (4):623.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • McNeill on Embodied Perception Theory.Søren Overgaard - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (254):135-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Dan Lloyd - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (2):289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Psychopsychology.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (4):264-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The brain as part of an enactive system.Shaun Gallagher, Daniel D. Hutto, Jan Slaby & Jonathan Cole - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (4):421-422.
    The notion of an enactive system requires thinking about the brain in a way that is different from the standard computational-representational models. In evolutionary terms, the brain does what it does and is the way that it is, across some scale of variations, because it is part of a living body with hands that can reach and grasp in certain limited ways, eyes structured to focus, an autonomic system, an upright posture, etc. coping with specific kinds of environments, and with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology.E. Husserl - 1960 - Philosophical Books 2 (2):4-5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   452 citations  
  • Perceiving: A Philosophical Study.R. J. Hirst - 1959 - Philosophical Quarterly 9 (37):366-373.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • Sense and Sensibilia.R. J. Hirst - 1963 - Philosophical Quarterly 13 (51):162-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Action in Perception by Alva Noë. [REVIEW]Alva Noë - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy 102 (5):259-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   770 citations  
  • Sense and Sensibilia.[author unknown] - 1962 - Foundations of Language 3 (3):303-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Experience and knowledge.A. Gupta - 2006 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations