Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Executions, Motivations, and Accomplishments.David Israel, John Perry & Syun Tutiya - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (4):515 - 540.
    Brutus wanted to kill Caesar. He believed that Caesar was an ordinary mortal, and that, given this, stabbing him (by which we mean plunging a knife into his heart) was a way of killing him. He thought that he could stab Caesar, for he remembered that he had a knife and saw that Caesar was standing next to him on his left, in the Forum. So Brutus was motivated to stab the man to his left. He did so, thereby killing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (1 other version)Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge.John McDowell - 1988 - In Jonathan Dancy (ed.), Perceptual knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 455-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   347 citations  
  • Past, Space, and Self.John Campbell - 1994 - MIT Press.
    In this book John Campbell shows that the general structural features of human thought can be seen as having their source in the distinctive ways in which we...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Individuals.P. F. Strawson - 1959 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 14 (2):246-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   897 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics.James Cargile - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):320-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   611 citations  
  • (1 other version)Practical Reflection, by J. David Velleman. [REVIEW]Michael H. Robins - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4):949-952.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Causality, interpretation, and the mind.William Child - 1994 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Philosophers of mind have long been interested in the relation between two ideas: that causality plays an essential role in our understanding of the mental; and that we can gain an understanding of belief and desire by considering the ascription of attitudes to people on the basis of what they say and do. Many have thought that those ideas are incompatible. William Child argues that there is in fact no tension between them, and that we should accept both. He shows (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • The integration of spatial vision and action.Bill Brewer - 1993 - In Naomi Eilan, Rosaleen A. McCarthy & Bill Brewer (eds.), Spatial representation: problems in philosophy and psychology. Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Circumstantial attitudes and benevolent cognition.John Perry - 1986 - In Jeremy Butterfield (ed.), Language, mind and logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    From: _Language, Mind and Logic_, edited by Jeremy Butter?eld. 123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Practical reflection.J. David Velleman - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):33-61.
    “What do you see when you look at your face in the mirror?” asks J. David Velleman in introducing his philosophical theory of action. He takes this simple act of self-scrutiny as a model for the reflective reasoning of rational agents: our efforts to understand our existence and conduct are aided by our efforts to make it intelligible. Reflective reasoning, Velleman argues, constitutes practical reasoning. By applying this conception, _Practical Reflection_ develops philosophical accounts of intention, free will, and the foundation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Recognizing friends by their walk: Gait perception without familiarity cues.James E. Cutting & Lynn T. Kozlowski - 1977 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 9 (5):353-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The ability to recognize oneself from a video recording of one’s movements without seeing one’s body.T. Beardsworth & T. Buckner - 1981 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 18 (1):19-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Causality, interpretation and the mind.William Child - 1994 - History of European Ideas 21 (4):612-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Past, Space, and Self.R. M. De Gaynesford - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (179):243-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Past, Space, and Self.Robert Hanna - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (1):102.
    Necessarily and trivially, ‘I’ means its occurrent utterer or thinker. But how is self-reference possible? Providing an adequate answer to this very hard question is the task undertaken by John Campbell in Past, Space, and Self. His answer, in a nutshell, is that the fundamental ground of self-reference is self-consciousness; and the bulk of the book is devoted to sketching the architecture of this cognitive capacity. Campbell wants to say that the essence of self-consciousness is given in the set of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations