Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Practice, reasons, and the agent's point of view.George Pavlakos - 2009 - Ratio Juris 22 (1):74-94.
    Positivism, in its standard outlook, is normative contextualism: If legal reasons are content-independent, then their content may vary with the context or point of view. Despite several advantages vis-à-vis strong metaphysical conceptions of reasons, contextualism implies relativism, which may lead further to the fragmentation of the point of view of agency. In his Oxford Hart Lecture, Coleman put forward a fresh account of the moral semantics of legal content, one that lays claim to preserving the unity of agency while retaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Structures of Normative Theories.James Dreier - 1993 - The Monist 76 (1):22-40.
    Normative theorists like to divide normative theories into classes. One special point of focus has been to place utilitarianism into a larger class of theories which do not necessarily share its view about what is alone of impersonal intrinsic value, namely, individual human well-being, but do share another structural feature, roughly its demand that each person seek to maximize the realization of what is of impersonal intrinsic value. The larger class is distinguished from its complement in two apparently different ways. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition.John Rawls - 1999 - Harvard University Press.
    Previous edition, 1st, published in 1971.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1765 citations  
  • The Morality of Freedom.Joseph Raz - 1986 - Philosophy 63 (243):119-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1015 citations  
  • Two Concepts of the Margin of Appreciation.George Letsas - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (4):705-732.
    The doctrine of the margin of appreciation that the European Court of Human Rights has developed in its case law has given rise to considerable criticism. In this article I draw a distinction between two different ways in which the Court has used the doctrine. The first one is in cases where the Court has to decide whether a particular interference with a Convention freedom is justified. In answering that question, the Court often uses the label ‘margin of appreciation’ without (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Wrongness and Reasons: A Re-examination.T. M. Scanlon - 2007 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 2:5-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Principles and Particularisms.Richard Holton - 2002 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 76 (1):191-209.
    Should particularists about ethics claim that moral principles are never true? Or should they rather claim that any finite set of principles will not be sufficient to capture ethics? This paper explores and defends the possibility of embracing the second of these claims whilst rejecting the first, a position termed 'principled particularism'. The main argument that particularists present for their position-the argument that holds that any moral conclusion can be superseded by further considerations-is quite compatible with principled particularism; indeed, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Altruism, solipsism, and the objectivity of reasons.Nicholas L. Sturgeon - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (3):374-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Equality, Responsibility, and the Law.Arthur Ripstein - 1999 - Law and Philosophy 20 (6):617-635.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations