Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Connexive implication.Storrs Mccall - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):415-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • (1 other version)A propositional logic with subjunctive conditionals.R. B. Angell - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):327-343.
    In this paper a formalized logic of propositions, PA1, is presented. It is proven consistent and its relationships to traditional logic, to PM ([15]), to subjunctive (including contrary-to-fact) implication and to the “paradoxes” of material and strict implication are developed. Apart from any intrinsic merit it possesses, its chief significance lies in demonstrating the feasibility of a general logic containing theprinciple of subjunctive contrariety, i.e., the principle that ‘Ifpwere true thenqwould be true’ and ‘Ifpwere true thenqwould be false’ are incompatible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • On systems containing Aristotle's thesis.R. Routley & H. Montgomery - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):82-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Modal logic with subjunctive conditionals and dispositional predicates.Lennart Åqvist - 1973 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (1):1 - 76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Relevant deduction.Gerhard Schurz - 1991 - Erkenntnis 35 (1):391 - 437.
    This paper presents an outline of a new theory of relevant deduction which arose from the purpose of solving paradoxes in various fields of analytic philosophy. In distinction to relevance logics, this approach does not replace classical logic by a new one, but distinguishes between relevance and validity. It is argued that irrelevant arguments are, although formally valid, nonsensical and even harmful in practical applications. The basic idea is this: a valid deduction is relevant iff no subformula of the conclusion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Semantics for connexive logics. I.Richard Routley - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (4):393 - 412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Strong Boethius' thesis and consequential implication.Claudio Pizzi & Timothy Williamson - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (5):569-588.
    The paper studies the relation between systems of modal logic and systems of consequential implication, a non-material form of implication satisfying "Aristotle's Thesis" (p does not imply not p) and "Weak Boethius' Thesis" (if p implies q, then p does not imply not q). Definitions are given of consequential implication in terms of modal operators and of modal operators in terms of consequential implication. The modal equivalent of "Strong Boethius' Thesis" (that p implies q implies that p does not imply (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Aristotle's thesis in consistent and inconsistent logics.Chris Mortensen - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (1-2):107 - 116.
    A typical theorem of conaexive logics is Aristotle''s Thesis(A), (AA).A cannot be added to classical logic without producing a trivial (Post-inconsistent) logic, so connexive logics typically give up one or more of the classical properties of conjunction, e.g.(A & B)A, and are thereby able to achieve not only nontriviality, but also (negation) consistency. To date, semantical modellings forA have been unintuitive. One task of this paper is to give a more intuitive modelling forA in consistent logics. In addition, while inconsistent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A Routley-Meyer affixing style semantics for logics containing Aristotle's Thesis.Ross T. Brady - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (2):235-241.
    We provide a semantics for relevant logics with addition of Aristotle's Thesis, ∼(A→∼A) and also Boethius,(A→B)→∼(A→∼B). We adopt the Routley-Meyer affixing style of semantics but include in the model structures a regulatory structure for all interpretations of formulae, with a view to obtaining a lessad hoc semantics than those previously given for such logics. Soundness and completeness are proved, and in the completeness proof, a new corollary to the Priming Lemma is introduced (c.f.Relevant Logics and their Rivals I, Ridgeview, 1982).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Decision procedures for logics of consequential implication.Claudio Pizzi - 1991 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32 (4):618-636.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Implicazione crisippea e dipendenza contestuale.C. Pizzi - 1998 - Dianoia 3:25-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why is conjunctive simplification invalid?Bruce E. R. Thompson - 1991 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32 (2):248-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • VIII.—On Entailment.S. Körner - 1947 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 47 (1):143-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Bolzano's consequence, relevance, and enthymemes.Rolf George - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (3):299 - 318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations