Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Collective Responsibility in a Hollywood Standoff.Sara Rachel Chant - 2015 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):83-92.
    In this paper, I advance a counterexample to the collective agency thesis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The responsibility of "random collections".Stanley Bates - 1971 - Ethics 81 (4):343-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The subject of “We intend”.Hans Bernhard Schmid - 2018 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (2):231-243.
    This paper examines and compares the ways in which intentions of the singular kind and the plural kind are subjective. Are intentions of the plural kind ours in the same way intentions of the singular kind are mine? Starting with the singular case, it is argued that “I intend” is subjective in virtue of self-knowledge. Self-knowledge is special in that it is self-identifying, self-validating, self-committing, and self-authorizing. Moving to the plural form, it is argued that in spite of apparent differences, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Plural self-awareness.Hans Bernhard Schmid - 2014 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (1):7-24.
    It has been claimed in the literature that collective intentionality and group attitudes presuppose some “sense of ‘us’” among the participants (other labels sometimes used are “sense of community,” “communal awareness,” “shared point of view,” or “we-perspective”). While this seems plausible enough on an intuitive level, little attention has been paid so far to the question of what the nature and role of this mysterious “sense of ‘us’” might be. This paper states (and argues for) the following five claims: (1) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Expressing Group Attitudes: On First Person Plural Authority.Hans Bernhard Schmid - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (S9):1685-1701.
    Under normal circumstances, saying that you have a thought, a belief, a desire, or an intention differs from saying that somebody (who happens to be you) has that attitude. The former statement comes with some form of first person authority and constitutes commitments that are not involved in the latter case. Speaking with first person authority, and thereby publicly committing oneself, is a practice that plays an important role in our communication and in our understanding of what it means to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What is an agent.Carol Rovane - 2004 - Synthese 140 (1-2):181 - 198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On Social Facts.Michael Root - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):675.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Can a random collection of individuals be morally responsible?Virginia Held - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (14):471-481.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • On Social Facts.Margaret Gilbert - 1989 - Ethics 102 (4):853-856.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   534 citations  
  • On knowing what we're doing together: groundless group self-knowledge and plural self-blindness.Hans Bernhard Schmid - 2016 - In Michael Brady & Miranda Fricker (eds.), The Epistemic Life of Groups: Essays in the Epistemology of Collectives. Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The First Person Perspective and Other Essays.Sydney Shoemaker - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 59 (2):378-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Sharing Responsibility.Michael J. Zimmerman - 1985 - American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (2):115 - 122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations