Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Democracy and Law: Situating Law within John Dewey's Democratic Vision.Brian E. Butler - 2010 - Etica & Politica 12 (1):256-280.
    In this paper I argue that John Dewey developed a philosophy of law that follows directly from his conception of democracy. Indeed, under Dewey’s theory an understanding of law can only follow from an accurate understanding of the social and political context within which it functions. This has important implications for the form law takes within democ- ratic society. The paper will explore these implications through a comparison of Dewey’s claims with those of Richard Posner and Ronald Dworkin; two other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Knowing and asserting.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    This paper aims to identify the constitutive rule of assertion, conceived by analogy with the rules of a game. That assertion has such rules is by no means obvious; perhaps it is more like a natural phenomenon than it seems. One way to find out is by supposing that it has such rules, in order to see where the hypothesis leads and what it explains. That will be done here. The hypothesis is not perfectly clear, of course, but we have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   333 citations  
  • Truth and the Past.Michael Dummett - 2003 - Cambridge University Press.
    Michael Dummett's three John Dewey Lectures--"The Concept of Truth," "Statements About the Past," and "The Metaphysics of Time"--were delivered at Columbia University in the spring of 2002. Revised and expanded, the lectures are presented here along with two new essays by Dummett, "Truth: Deniers and Defenders" and "The Indispensability of the Concept of Truth." In _Truth and the Past,_ Dummett clarifies his current positions on the metaphysical issue of realism and the philosophy of language. He is best known as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • On Logic in the Law: "Something, but not All".Susan Haack - 2007 - Ratio Juris 20 (1):1-31.
    In 1880, when Oliver Wendell Holmes (later to be a Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court) criticized the logical theology of law articulated by Christopher Columbus Langdell (the first Dean of Harvard Law School), neither Holmes nor Langdell was aware of the revolution in logic that had begun, the year before, with Frege's Begriffsschrift. But there is an important element of truth in Holmes's insistence that a legal system cannot be adequately understood as a system of axioms and corollaries; and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)``Knowing and Asserting".Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    Assertions are praised as true, informative, relevant, sincere, warranted, well-phrased, or polite. They are criticized as false, uninformative, irrelevant, insincere, unwarranted, ill-phrased, or rude. Sometimes they deserve such praise or criticism. If any respect in which performances of an act can deserve praise or criticism is a norm for that act, then the speech act of assertion has many norms. So has almost any act; jumps can deserve praise as long or brave, criticism as short or cowardly. But it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Truth and Justice, Inquiry and Advocacy, Science and Law.Susan Haack - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (1):15-26.
    There is tension between the adversarialism of the U.S. legal culture and the investigative procedures of the sciences, and between the law's concern for finality and the open‐ended fallibilism of science. A long history of attempts to domesticate scientific testimony by legal rules of admissibility has left federal judges with broad screening responsibilities; recent adaptations of adversarialism in the form of court‐appointed experts have been criticized as “inquisitorial,” even “undemocratic.” In exploring their benefits and disadvantages, it would make sense to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Sigwart, Husserl and Frege on truth and logic, or is psychologism still a threat?Eva Picardi - 1997 - European Journal of Philosophy 5 (2):162–182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dispositional belief, assent, and acceptance.Pascal Engel - 1999 - Dialectica 53 (3-4):211–226.
    I discuss Ruth Marcus' conception of beliefs as dispositional states related to possible states of affaires. While I agree with Marcus that this conception accounts for the necessary distinction between belief and linguistic assent, I argue that the relationship between dispositional beliefs and our assent attitudes is more complex, and should include other mental states, such as acceptances, which, although they contain voluntary elements, are further layers of dispositional doxastic attitudes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Saving Pragmatist Democratic Theory.Robert Talisse - 2010 - Etica E Politica 12 (1):12-27.
    Deweyan democracy is inherently comprehensive in the Rawlsian sense and therefore unable to countenance the fact of reasonable pluralism. This renders Deweyan democracy nonviable on pragmatic grounds. Given the Deweyan pragmatists’ views about the proper relation between philosophy and politics, unless there is a viable pragmatist alternative to Deweyan democracy, pragmatism itself is jeopardized. I develop a pragmatist alternative to Deweyan democracy rooted in a Peircean social epistemology. Peircean democracy can give Deweyan pragmatists all they should want from a democratic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logique, psychologie et métaphysique: Les fondements du pragmatisme selon C. S. Peirce.Claudine Engel-Tiercelin - 1985 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 16 (2):229-250.
    The originality of Peirce's pragmatism is grounded in the very early project Peirce draws of a Logic, in which psychology and metaphysics are intimately connected: under the influence of Kant, Boole and the Scolastics, and through a certain logical use of the sign, Peirce elaborates a Logic, both more formal and larger , on the Scotistic model of a Speculative Grammar.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ethics Without Ontology.Hilary Putnam - 2004 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In this brief book one of the most distinguished living American philosophers takes up the question of whether ethical judgments can properly be considered objective--a question that has vexed philosophers over the past century. Reviewing what he deems the disastrous consequences of ontology's influence on analytic philosophy--in particular, the contortions it imposes upon debates about the objective of ethical judgments--Putnam proposes abandoning the very idea of ontology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Moral Reasons.Jonathan Dancy - 1993 - Philosophy 69 (267):114-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   319 citations  
  • (6 other versions)Peirce.Christopher Hookway - 1985 - Mind 95 (377):138-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • (1 other version)Responsible for Truth? Peirce on Judgment and Assertion.G. Tuzet - 2006 - Cognitio 7:317-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Formal legal truth and substantive truth in judicial fact-finding -- their justified divergence in some particular cases.Robert S. Summers - 1999 - Law and Philosophy 18 (5):497 - 511.
    Truth is a fundamental objective of adjudicative processes; ideally, substantive as distinct from formal legal truth. But problems of evidence, for example, may frustrate finding of substantive truth; other values may lead to exclusions of probative evidence, e.g., for the sake of fairness. Jury nullification and jury equity. Limits of time, and definitiveness of decision, require allocation of burden of proof. Degree of truth-formality is variable within a system and across systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logique, psychologie et métaphysique: les fondements du pragmatisme selon C. S. Peirce.Claudine Engel-Tiercelin - 1985 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 16 (2):229-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Robert B. Brandom, Making It Explicit. Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.Michael Esfeld - 1999 - Erkenntnis 51 (2-3):333-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Frege: An Introduction to His Philosophy. [REVIEW]David Bell - 1984 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 21:207-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Frege. [REVIEW]David Bell - 1984 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 21:207-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • L'abduzione percettiva in Peirce.G. Tuzet - 2003 - Aquinas 46 (2-3):307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation