Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Harm to Self: The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law.Joel Feinberg - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (1):129-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Disclosure and Consent to Medical Research Participation.Danielle Bromwich & Joseph Millum - 2013 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (4):195-219.
    Most regulations and guidelines require that potential research participants be told a great deal of information during the consent process. Many of these documents, and most of the scholars who consider the consent process, assume that all this information must be disclosed because it must all be understood. However, a wide range of studies surveying apparently competent participants in clinical trials around the world show that many do not understand key aspects of what they have been told. The standard view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Deciding for Others.Gerald Dworkin, Allen E. Buchanan & Dan W. Brock - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162):118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Voluntariness of Consent to Research: A Conceptual Model.Paul S. Appelbaum, Charles W. Lidz & Robert Klitzman - 2009 - Hastings Center Report 39 (1):30-39.
    Voluntariness of consent to research has not been sufficiently explored through empirical research. The aims of this study were to develop a more comprehensive approach to assessing voluntariness and to generate preliminary data on the extent and correlates of limitations on voluntariness. We developed a questionnaire to evaluate subjects’ reported motivations and constraints on voluntariness. 88 subjects in five different areas of clinical research—substance abuse, cancer, HIV, interventional cardiology, and depression—were assessed. Subjects reported a variety of motivations for participation. Offers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Ethics, deception, and 'those Milgram experiments'.C. D. Herrera - 2001 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (3):245–256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Counterfactual Consent and the Use of Deception in Research.Alan T. Wilson - 2014 - Bioethics 29 (7):470-477.
    The use of deception for the purposes of research is a widespread practice within many areas of study. If we want to avoid either absolute acceptance or absolute rejection of this practice then we require some method of distinguishing between those uses of deception which are morally acceptable and those which are not. In this article I discuss the concept of counterfactual consent, and propose a related distinction between counterfactual-defeating deception and counterfactual-compatible deception. The aim is to show that this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Exploring the ethics and psychological impact of deception in psychological research.M. H. Boynton, D. B. Portnoy & B. T. Johnson - 2013 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 35 (2):7-13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Disclosure and Consent to Medical Research Participation.Danielle Bromwich & Joseph Millum - 2015 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (2):195-219.
    Most regulations and guidelines require that potential research participants be told a great deal of information during the consent process. Many of these documents, and most of the scholars who consider the consent process, assume that all this information must be disclosed because it must all be understood. However, a wide range of studies surveying apparently competent participants in clinical trials around the world show that many do not understand key aspects of what they have been told. The standard view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Disclosure and Consent to Medical Research Participation.Danielle Bromwich & Joseph Millum - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4).
    Most regulations and guidelines require that potential research participants be told a great deal of information during the consent process. Many of these documents, and most of the scholars who consider the consent process, assume that all this information must be disclosed because it must all be understood. However, a wide range of studies surveying apparently competent participants in clinical trials around the world show that many do not understand key aspects of what they have been told. The standard view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Shading the Truth in Seeking Informed Consent for Research Purposes.Sissela Bok - 1995 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5 (1):1-17.
    I want to argue for two propositions. First, I suggest that what some researchers may take to be a simple trade-off between minor violations of the truth for the sake of access to far greater truths represents a profound miscalculation with far-reaching and cumulative reverberations. Second, I submit that today's research environment, as demanding, competitive, and sometimes bewildering as it is, offers genuine scope for what Murdoch calls truth-seeking, for imagining and questioning, and for relating to facts through both truth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Deception methods in psychology: Have they changed in 23 years?Joan E. Sieber, Rebecca Iannuzzo & Beverly Rodriguez - 1995 - Ethics and Behavior 5 (1):67 – 85.
    To learn whether criticism and regulation of research practices have been followed by a reduction of deception or use of more acceptable approaches to deception, the contents of all 1969, 1978, 1986, and 1992 issues of the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology were examined. Deception research was coded according to type of (non)informing (e.g., false informing, consent to deception, no informing), possible harmfulness of deception employed (e.g., powerfulness of induction, morality of the behavior induced, privacy of behavior), method of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Use of Deception in Public Health Behavioral Intervention Trials: A Case Study of Three Online Alcohol Trials.Jim McCambridge, Kypros Kypri, Preben Bendtsen & John Porter - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (11):39-47.
    Some public health behavioral intervention research studies involve deception. A methodological imperative to minimize bias can be in conflict with the ethical principle of informed consent. As a case study, we examine the specific forms of deception used in three online randomized controlled trials evaluating brief alcohol interventions. We elaborate our own decision making about the use of deception in these trials, and present our ongoing findings and uncertainties. We discuss the value of the approach of pragmatism for examining these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Consenting in the Dark: Choose Your Own Deception.Rachel Zuraw - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (11):57-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Voluntary Consent: Why a Value-Neutral Concept Won't Work.A. Wertheimer - 2012 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (3):226-254.
    Some maintain that voluntariness is a value-neutral concept. On that view, someone acts involuntarily if subject to a controlling influence or has no acceptable alternatives. I argue that a value-neutral conception of voluntariness cannot explain when and why consent is invalid and that we need a moralized account of voluntariness. On that view, most concerns about the voluntariness of consent to participate in research are not well founded.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • When Scientists Deceive: Applying the Federal Regulations.Collin C. O'Neil & Franklin G. Miller - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (2):344-350.
    Deception is a useful methodological device for studying attitudes and behavior, but deceptive studies fail to fulfill the informed consent requirements in the U.S. federal regulations. This means that before they can be approved by Institutional Review Boards, they must satisfy the four regulatory conditions for a waiver or alteration of these requirements. To illustrate our interpretation, we apply the conditions to a recent study that used deception to show that subjects judged the same wine as more enjoyable when they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Deceived versus nondeceived participants' perceptions of scientific and applied psychology.Elizabeth Soliday & Annette L. Stanton - 1995 - Ethics and Behavior 5 (1):87 – 104.
    Research examining the possible effects of deceptive research participation on participants' perceptions of psychology has yielded equivocal results. The present study's goal was to clarify the possible effects of participation in mildly deceptive research on participants' impressions of scientific and applied psychology. Participants (N = 112) were randomly assigned to one of six experimental conditions: active groups receiving negative, positive, or no feedback, or passive groups receiving negative, positive, or no feedback. Following participation, participants completed measures of impressions of psychotherapy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Forgoing Debriefing in Deceptive Research: Is It Ever Ethical?Roseanna Sommers & Franklin G. Miller - 2013 - Ethics and Behavior 23 (2):98-116.
    The use of deception in research is generally permitted so long as participants are debriefed at the conclusion of their participation. Several authoritative research ethics guidelines allow investigators to omit debriefing under certain circumstances, however. Here we examine various justifications for forgoing debriefing in deceptive research, including concerns about subject pool contamination, the risk that revealing the deception will be harmful or distressing to participants, and issues of practicability. We conclude that, contrary to current practice, omitting debriefing is ethically acceptable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Investigator's Duty Not to Deceive.Brian Cupples & Myron Gochnauer - 1985 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 7 (5):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How (Un)Acceptable Is Research Involving Deception?Charles P. Smith - 1981 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 3 (8):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations