Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Cognition is not computation: The argument from irreversibility.Selmer Bringsjord - 1997 - Synthese 113 (2):285-320.
    The dominant scientific and philosophical view of the mind – according to which, put starkly, cognition is computation – is refuted herein, via specification and defense of the following new argument: Computation is reversible; cognition isn't; ergo, cognition isn't computation. After presenting a sustained dialectic arising from this defense, we conclude with a brief preview of the view we would put in place of the cognition-is-computation doctrine.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Logic of Appearance: Dennett, Phenomenology and Psychoanalysis.Jasper Feyaerts & Stijn Vanheule - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searle on the Brink.Selmer Bringsjord - 1994 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 1.
    In his recent _The Rediscovery of the Mind_ John Searle tries to destroy cognitive science _and_ preserve a future in which a ``perfect science of the brain'' (1992, p. 235) arrives. I show that Searle can't accomplish both objectives. The ammunition he uses to realise the first stirs up a maelstrom of consciousness so wild it precludes securing the second.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Goldman has not defeated folk functionalism.James H. Fetzer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):42-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creative thinking presupposes the capacity for thought.James H. Fetzer - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical issues about perception.Austen Clark - 2003 - In L. Nadel (ed.), Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Nature Publishing Group.
    the philosophical regions. I will identify three: three obvious zones of The first and third of these kinds of problem are studied almost tectonic conflict within contemporary cognitive approaches to exclusively within departments of philosophy. Applied to perception.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Putting the brakes on enactive perception.Jesse J. Prinz - 2006 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12.
    Alva Noë’s _Action in Perception _offers a provocative and vigorous defense of the thesis that vision is enactive: visual experience depends on dispositional motor responses. On this view, vision and action are inextricably bound. In this review, I argue against enactive perception. I raise objections to seven lines of evidence that appear in Noë’s book, and I indicate some reasons for thinking that vision can operate independently of motor responses. I conclude that the relationship between vision and action is causal, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Thought insertion and self-knowledge.Jordi Fernández - 2010 - Mind and Language 25 (1):66-88.
    I offer an account of thought insertion based on a certain model of self-knowledge. I propose that subjects with thought insertion do not experience being committed to some of their own beliefs. A hypothesis about self-knowledge explains why. According to it, we form beliefs about our own beliefs on the basis of our evidence for them. First, I will argue that this hypothesis explains the fact that we feel committed to those beliefs which we are aware of. Then, I will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • How Neurons Mean: A Neurocomputational Theory of Representational Content.Chris Eliasmith - 2000 - Dissertation, Washington University in St. Louis
    Questions concerning the nature of representation and what representations are about have been a staple of Western philosophy since Aristotle. Recently, these same questions have begun to concern neuroscientists, who have developed new techniques and theories for understanding how the locus of neurobiological representation, the brain, operates. My dissertation draws on philosophy and neuroscience to develop a novel theory of representational content.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • An epistemological theory of consciousness?Pete Mandik - 2008 - In Alessio Plebe & Vivian M. De La Cruz (eds.), Philosophy in the Neuroscience Era. Squilibri.
    This article tackles problems concerning the reduction of phenomenal consciousness to brain processes that arise in consideration of specifically epistemological properties that have been attributed to conscious experiences. In particular, various defenders of dualism and epiphenomenalism have argued for their positions by assuming special epistemic access to phenomenal consciousness. Many physicalists have reacted to such arguments by denying the epistemological premises. My aim in this paper is to take a different approach in opposing dualism and argue that when we correctly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Introduction.Michel Ferrari - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (3):1-14.
    The history of the science of consciousness is difficult to trace because it involves an ongoing debate over the aims involved in the study of consciousness that historically engaged people working in a variety of different, often overlapping, philosophical projects. At least three main aims of these different projects can be identified: (1) providing an ultimate foundation for natural science; (2) providing an empirical study of experience; and (3) promoting human well-being by relieving suffering and encouraging human flourishing. Each of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How the Neuroscience of Decision Making Informs Our Conception of Autonomy.Gidon Felsen & Peter B. Reiner - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 2 (3):3-14.
    Autonomy, the ability to make decisions for ourselves about ourselves, is among the most prized of human liberties. In this review we reconsider the key conditions necessary for autonomous decision making, long debated by moral philosophers and ethicists, in light of current neuroscientific evidence. The most widely accepted criteria for autonomy are that decisions are made by a rationally deliberative and reflective agent and that these decisions are free of undue external influences. The corpus of neuroscientific data suggest that human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Enactivist vision.Jerome A. Feldman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):35-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Is consciousness of perception really separable from perception?Martha J. Farah - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):254-255.
    Although not the main point of his target article, Block defends the view that perception and awareness of perception could be functions of different brain systems. I will argue that the available data do not support this view, and that Block's defense of the view rests on problematic eonstruals of the “executive system” and of the components of information-processing models.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • One Damned Thing before Another.Francis Fallon - 2018 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 26 (1):90-105.
    The relation of man to his environment is the relation of the historian to his theme.The individual apart from society would be both speechless and mindless.In every other European language, the eq...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mosaic evolution of the neocortex.Dean Falk & Bruce Dudek - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):701-702.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Multiscale modeling of the brain should be validated in more detail against the biological data.Harry R. Erwin - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):297-298.
    Wright & Liley provide an advance in addressing the interaction of multiple scales of processing in the brain. It should address in more detail the biological evidence that underlies the models it proposes to replace.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implicit practical learning.Elizabeth Ennen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):404-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context and consciousness.Colin G. Ellard - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):681-682.
    The commentary argues that we cannot be sure that human consciousness has survival value and that in order to understand the origins and, perhaps, the function of consciousness, we should examine the behavioural and neural precursors to consciousness in nonhumans. An example is given of research on the role of context in decisions regarding fleeing from probable predators in the Mongolian gerbil.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Epistemic Warrants and Higher-Order Theories of Conscious Perception.James Edwards & Dimitris Platchias - 2016 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly:343-364.
    We present a new account of perceptual consciousness, one which gives due weight to the epistemic commitment of normal perception in familiar circumstances. The account is given in terms of a higher-order attitude for which the subject has an immediate perceptual epistemic warrant in the form of an appropriate first-order perception. We develop our account in contrast to Rosenthal's higher-order account, rejecting his view of consciousness in virtue of so-called ‘targetless’ higher-order states. We explain the key notion of an immediate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The modern mind: Its missing parts?R. I. M. Dunbar - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):758-759.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • On the origins of language: A history of constraints and windows of opportunity.R. I. M. Dunbar - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):721-735.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Goals, analogy, and the social constraints of scientific discovery.Kevin Dunbar & Lisa M. Baker - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):538-539.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ce que l'on peut apprendre sur les chauves-souris à l'aide d'une télé couleur.Paul Dumouchel - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (3):493-.
    Deux ou trois articles récents, Nagel, Block, Jackson, forment la toile de fond de discussions actuelles au sujet des qualia et du caractère subjectif de l'expérience, du moins en philosophie de l'esprit. Ces articles ont ceci en commun qu'ils visent tous à montrer qu'un certain aspect de l'expérience consciente – les qualia ou sa dimension subjective – remet en cause l'une ou l'autre, ou l'ensemble de nos théories psychophysiques. Ce qui est visé, au-delà des théories psychophysiques, c'est le physicalisme, entendu (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language and levels of selection.Lee Alan Dugatkin & David Sloan Wilson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):701-701.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The new naturalism.Don Dedrick - 1993 - Metaphilosophy 24 (4):390-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation: Part of the problem of creativity.Merlin Donald - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):537-538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Too much ado about belief.Jérôme Dokic & Elisabeth Pacherie - 2007 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 (1-2):185-200.
    Three commitments guide Dennett’s approach to the study of consciousness. First, an ontological commitment to materialist monism. Second, a methodological commitment to what he calls ‘heterophenomenology.’ Third, a ‘doxological’ commitment that can be expressed as the view that there is no room for a distinction between a subject’s beliefs about how things seem to her and what things actually seem to her, or, to put it otherwise, as the view that there is no room for a reality/appearance distinction for consciousness. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Unified cognitive theory is not comprehensive.P. C. Dodwell - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):443-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • I in an other’s eye.Alan Dix - 2019 - AI and Society 34 (1):55-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Breakthrough on the consciousness front or much ado about nothing?N. F. Dixon - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):253-254.
    Propositions as to the nature of consciousness, based on disorders of perception that result from brain damage, and taking insufficient account of the numerous ways in which normal subjects may deviate from that “usual” sequence of events (input → subjective awareness → output) risk increasing rather than diminishing any existing confusion about the function of consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dynamic and recursive interplay of embodiment and narrative identity.Roy Dings - 2018 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (2):186-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Complex behaviors: Evolution and the brain.William O. Dingwall - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):186-188.
    Three issues are addressed in this commentary. (1) Wilkins & Wakefield are commended for placing the complex behavior they discuss within an evolutionary matrix. (2) They err on a number of points in regard to their treatment of this complex behavior. These involve (a) their emphasis on the evolution of conceptual structure rather than language, (b) their equation of meaning with reference, (c) their minimalist view of learning theory, and (d) their separation of the evolution of speech from that of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A patterned process approach to brain, consciousness, and behavior.José-Luis Díaz - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (2):179-195.
    The architecture of brain, consciousness, and behavioral processes is shown to be formally similar in that all three may be conceived and depicted as Petri net patterned processes structured by a series of elements occurring or becoming active in stochastic succession, in parallel, with different rhythms of temporal iteration, and with a distinct qualitative manifestation in the spatiotemporal domain. A patterned process theory is derived from the isomorphic features of the models and contrasted with connectionist, dynamic system notions. This empirically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Empathy and Openness: Practices of Intersubjectivity at the Core of the Science of Consciousness.Natalie Depraz & Diego Cosmelli - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (sup1):163-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Part of Cognitive Science That Is Philosophy.Daniel C. Dennett - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (2):231--236.
    There is much good work for philosophers to do in cognitive science if they adopt the constructive attitude that prevails in science, work toward testable hypotheses, and take on the task of clarifying the relationship between the scientific concepts and the everyday concepts with which we conduct our moral lives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review of Other Minds: the octopus, the sea and the deep origins of consciousness: Peter Godfrey-Smith, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, NY, 2016. [REVIEW]Daniel Dennett - 2019 - Biology and Philosophy 34 (1):2.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Overworking the hippocampus.Daniel C. Dennett - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):677-678.
    Gray mistakenly thinks I have rejected the sort of theoretical enterprise he is undertaking, because, according to him, I think that "more data" is all that is needed to resolve all the issues. Not at all. My stalking horse was the bizarre (often pathetic) claim that no amount of empirical, "third-person point-of-view" science (data plus theory) could ever reduce the residue of mystery about consciousness to zero. This "New Mysterianism" (Flanagan, 1991) is one that he should want to combat as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hitting the nail on the head.Daniel C. Dennett - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):35-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Counting consciousnesses: None, one, two, or none of the above?Daniel C. Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):178.
    In a second there is also time enough, we might add. In his dichotomizing fervor, Bogen fails to realize that our argument is neutral with respect to the number of consciousnesses that inhabit the normal or the split-brain skull. Should there be two, for instance, we would point out that within the neural network that subserves each, no privileged locus should be postulated. (Midline location is not the issue--it was only a minor issue for Descartes, in fact.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Productance physicalism and a posteriori necessity.Don Dedrick - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):28-29.
    The problem of nonreflectors perceived as colored is the central problem for Byrne & Hilbert's (B&H's) physicalism. Vision scientists and other interested parties need to consider the motivation for their account of “productance physicalism.” Is B&H's theory motivated by scientific concerns or by philosophical interests intended to preserve a physicalist account of color as a posteriori necessary?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Orange laser beams are not illusory: The need for a plurality of “real” color ontologies.Lieven Decock & Jaap van Brakel - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):27-28.
    Reflectance physicalism only provides a partial picture of the ontology of color. Byrne & Hilbert’ account is unsatisfactory because the replacement of reflectance functions by productance functions is ad hoc, unclear, and only leads to new problems. Furthermore, the effects of color contrast and differences in illumination are not really taken seriously: Too many “real” colors are tacitly dismissed as illusory, and this for arbitrary reasons. We claim that there cannot be an all-embracing ontology for color.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hunting for consciousness in the brain: What is (the name of) the game?José-Luis Díaz - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):679-680.
    Robust theories concerning the connection between consciousness and brain function should derive not only from empirical evidence but also from a well grounded inind-body ontology. In the case of the comparator hypothesis, Gray develops his ideas relying extensively on empirical evidence, but he bounces irresolutely among logically incompatible metaphysical theses which, in turn, leads him to excessively skeptical conclusions concerning the naturalization of consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What is a colour space?Jules Davidoff - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Examples as method? My attempts to understand assessment and fairness (in the spirit of the later wittgenstein).Andrew Davis - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (3):371-389.
    What is 'fairness' in the context of educational assessment? I apply this question to a number of contemporary educational assessment practices and policies. My approach to philosophy of education owes much to Wittgenstein. A commentary set apart from the main body of the paper focuses on my style of philosophising. Wittgenstein teaches us to examine in depth the fine-grained complexities of social phenomena and to refrain from imposing abstract theory on a recalcitrant reality. I write philosophy of education for policy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Examples as Method? My Attempts to Understand Assessment and Fairness (in the Spirit of the Later Wittgenstein).Andrew Davis - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (3):371-389.
    What is ‘fairness’ in the context of educational assessment? I apply this question to a number of contemporary educational assessment practices and policies. My approach to philosophy of education owes much to Wittgenstein. A commentary set apart from the main body of the paper focuses on my style of philosophising. Wittgenstein teaches us to examine in depth the fine-grained complexities of social phenomena and to refrain from imposing abstract theory on a recalcitrant reality. I write philosophy of education for policy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Creativity, combination, and cognition.Terry Dartnall - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):537-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Color is as color does.James L. Dannemiller - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The selfless consciousness.Antonio R. Damasio - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):208-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Phillips on Unconscious Perception and Overflow.Nicholas D’Aloisio-Montilla - 2019 - Philosophia 47 (3):649-662.
    Phillips argues that Block faces a “serious internal challenge” in defending the claim that unconscious perception is of the same fundamental kind as conscious perception. This challenge is said to result from Block’s commitment to phenomenal overflow. However, in this paper, I demonstrate that Phillips’ rejection of overflow likewise renders his view on unconscious perception “internally challenged” and therefore equally problematic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations