Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Phase semantics and sequent calculus for pure noncommutative classical linear propositional logic.V. Michele Abrusci - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1403-1451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Contrary-to-Duty Reasoning: A Categorical Approach.Clayton Peterson - 2015 - Logica Universalis 9 (1):47-92.
    This paper provides an analysis of contrary-to-duty reasoning from the proof-theoretical perspective of category theory. While Chisholm’s paradox hints at the need of dyadic deontic logic by showing that monadic deontic logics are not able to adequately model conditional obligations and contrary-to-duties, other arguments can be objected to dyadic approaches in favor of non-monotonic foundations. We show that all these objections can be answered at one fell swoop by modeling conditional obligations within a deductive system defined as an instance of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Temporal non-commutative logic: Expressing time, resource, order and hierarchy.Norihiro Kamide - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (2):97-126.
    A first-order temporal non-commutative logic TN[l], which has no structural rules and has some l-bounded linear-time temporal operators, is introduced as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. The logic TN[l] allows us to provide not only time-dependent, resource-sensitive, ordered, but also hierarchical reasoning. Decidability, cut-elimination and completeness (w.r.t. phase semantics) theorems are shown for TN[l]. An advantage of TN[l] is its decidability, because the standard first-order linear-time temporal logic is undecidable. A correspondence theorem between TN[l] and a resource indexed non-commutative logic RN[l] (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a Semantic Characterization of Cut-Elimination.Agata Ciabattoni & Kazushige Terui - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (1):95-119.
    We introduce necessary and sufficient conditions for a (single-conclusion) sequent calculus to admit (reductive) cut-elimination. Our conditions are formulated both syntactically and semantically.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The finite model property for various fragments of intuitionistic linear logic.Mitsuhiro Okada & Kazushige Terui - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):790-802.
    Recently Lafont [6] showed the finite model property for the multiplicative additive fragment of linear logic (MALL) and for affine logic (LLW), i.e., linear logic with weakening. In this paper, we shall prove the finite model property for intuitionistic versions of those, i.e. intuitionistic MALL (which we call IMALL), and intuitionistic LLW (which we call ILLW). In addition, we shall show the finite model property for contractive linear logic (LLC), i.e., linear logic with contraction, and for its intuitionistic version (ILLC). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • European Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.E. -J. Thiele - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (1):282-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Monoidal logics: completeness and classical systems.Clayton Peterson - 2019 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 29 (2):121-151.
    ABSTRACTMonoidal logics were introduced as a foundational framework to analyze the proof theory of logical systems. Inspired by Lambek's seminal work in categorical logic, the objective is to defin...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamic non-commutative logic.Norihiro Kamide - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (1):33-51.
    A first-order dynamic non-commutative logic, which has no structural rules and has some program operators, is introduced as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. Decidability, cut-elimination and completeness theorems are shown for DN or its fragments. DN is intended to represent not only program-based, resource-sensitive, ordered, sequence-based, but also hierarchical reasoning.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic of Dynamics and Dynamics of Logic: Some Paradigm Examples.Bob Coecke, David J. Moore & Sonja Smets - 2004 - In S. Rahman (ed.), Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 527--555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations