Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. II.3 What is TRASP?: The Radical Programme as a Methodological Imperative.H. M. Collins - 1981 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 11 (2):215-224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The missing syntheses in the historiography of science.Casper Hakfoort - 1991 - History of Science 29 (84):207-216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • History of science for its own sake?Steve Fuller - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (4):95-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Positivism, whiggism, and the Chemical Revolution: A study in the historiography of chemistry.John G. McEvoy - 1997 - History of Science 35 (107):1-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Philosopher and the Revolutionary State: How Karl Popper’s Ideas Shaped the Views of Iranian Intellectuals.Ali Paya & Mohammad Amin Ghaneirad - 2006 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20 (2):185 – 213.
    The present paper is an attempt to explore the impact of Karl Popper's ideas on the views of a number of intellectual groups in post-revolutionary Iran. Throughout the text, we have tried to make use of original sources and our own personal experiences. The upshot of the arguments of the paper is that the Viennese philosopher has made a long-lasting impression on the intellectual scene of present-day Iran in that even those socio-political groups which are not in favour of his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Observations on the History of Science in Italy.Maurizio Torrini - 1988 - British Journal for the History of Science 21 (4):427-446.
    In two conferences, separated by the space of only a few months, in September 1966 and March 1967, Giovanni Polvani—at the time president of the Domus Galilaeana—and the council of the Domus, attempted a series of operations, all ambitious and difficult. The first, and to some extent the simplest, was to gather round the Domus all those who were working in a professional role or as amateurs on the history of science. Also invited were scholars who had become involved in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the independence of singular causal explanation in social science: Archaeology.Thomas Nickles - 1977 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (2):163-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Turner on Merton.Joseph Agassi - 2009 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (2):284-293.
    Stephen Turner complains about weaknesses of Robert K. Merton's teachings without noticing that these are common. He puts down Merton's ideas despite his innovations, on the ground that they are not successful and not sufficiently revolutionary. The criteria by which he condemns Merton are too vague and too high. Merton's merit is in his having put the sociology of science on the map and drawn attention to the egalitarianism that was prominent in classical science and that is now diminished. Key (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Towards a theory of openness to criticism.Tom Settle, I. C. Jarvie & Joseph Agassi - 1974 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4 (1):83-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Why should I read histories of science? A response to Patricia Fara, Steve Fuller and Joseph Rouse.Mark Erickson - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (4):68-91.
    History of science is, we are told, an important subject for study. Its rise in recent years to become a ‘stand alone’ discipline has been mirrored by an expansion of popular history of science texts available in bookstores. Given this, it is perhaps surprising that little attention has been given to how history of science is written. This article attempts to do that through constructing a typology of histories of science based upon a consideration of audiences who read these texts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Procrustean psychiatry.Nathaniel Laor - 1985 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 15 (3):333-347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ampère, the Etherians, and the Oersted Connexion.Kenneth L. Caneva - 1980 - British Journal for the History of Science 13 (2):121-138.
    In 1826 André-Marie Ampère published the ‘Mathematical theory of electrodynamic phenomena, uniquely derived from experiment’, in which he showed how the mathematical law for the force between current elements could be derived from four ingenious equilibrium experiments. He made a great show of following a Newtonian inductivist methodology, and his law, like Newton's for gravitation, was presented as a purely descriptive mathematical expression for a certain class of phenomena, one for which its author did not provide any causal or ontological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • How Do We Learn from Argument?: Toward an Account of the Logic of Problems.Terry M. Goode & John R. Wettersten - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (4):673-689.
    From the pre-Socratics to the present, one primary aim of philosophy has been to learn from arguments. Philosophers have debated whether we could indeed do this, but they have by and large agreed on how we would use arguments if learning from argument was at all possible. They have agreed that we could learn from arguments either by starting with true premises and validly deducing further statements which must also be true and therefore constitute new knowledge, or that we could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations