Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Presupposing Legal Authority.Robert Mullins - 2022 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 42 (2):411-437.
    The thesis that law necessarily claims authority is popular amongst legal philosophers. Some distinguished legal philosophers, including the late John Gardner, Joseph Raz and Scott Shapiro, have suggested that support for this thesis is found in legal officials’ use of deontic language. This article begins by considering the merits of this suggestion. I discuss two unpromising arguments for the claim thesis based on the use of deontic language in law. I then suggest that a more plausible basis for the claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Limits of Institutionalised Legal Discourse.Emmanuel Melissaris - 2005 - Ratio Juris 18 (4):464-483.
    . One of the most powerful accounts of the necessary connection between law and morality grounded on the openness of communication is provided by Robert Alexy, who builds a discourse theory of law on the basis of Habermas’ theory of general practical discourse. In this article I argue that the thesis based on the openness of legal discourse is problematic in that it does not provide a convincing account of the differentiation of legal discourse from other practical discourses. I offer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • When Is a Regime Not a Legal System? Alexy on Moral Correctness and Social Efficacy.David H. McIlroy - 2013 - Ratio Juris 26 (1):65-84.
    Robert Alexy defines law as including a claim to moral correctness and demonstrating social efficacy. This paper argues that law's social efficacy is not merely an observable fact but is undergirded by moral commitments by rulers that it is possible for their subjects to follow the rules, that the rulers and others will also follow the rules, that subjects will be protected from violence if they act in accordance with the rules, and that subjects will be entitled to legal redress (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Is the Rule of Law a Limit on Power?David McIlroy - 2016 - Studies in Christian Ethics 29 (1):34-50.
    A commitment to the rule of law is a commitment to the governance of a society through the use of general or generalisable rules which are binding on both the subjects and the rulers. By giving due notice of the rules and of any changes to them, those who are subject to the law are protected from violence and enabled to act as agents. This is the essential contribution the rule of law makes to important human goods including freedom. Such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kelsen's Pallid Normativity.James W. Harris - 1996 - Ratio Juris 9 (1):94-117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some Problems with Robert Alexy's Account of Legal Validity: The Relevance of the Participant's Perspective.Paula Gaido - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (3):381-392.
    This article examines Robert Alexy's account of legal validity. It concludes that Alexy's account of legal validity lacks sufficient support given the author's methodological commitments. To reach that conclusion, it assesses the plausibility of simultaneously maintaining that the participant's perspective has conceptual privilege in the explanation of the nature of law, that legal discourse is a special case of general practical discourse, and that unjust considerations can be legally valid norms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Law and moral justification.Andrea Faggion - 2020 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 61 (145):55-72.
    ABSTRACT Many prominent legal philosophers believe that law makes some type of moral claim in virtue of its nature. Although the law is not an intelligent agent, the attribution of a claim to law does not need to be as mysterious as some theorists believe. It means that law-making and law- applying acts are intelligible only in the light of a certain presupposition, even if a lawmaker or a law-applier subjectively disbelieves the content of that presupposition. In this paper, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Habermas, modernity and law: A bibliography.Mathieu Deflem - 1994 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 20 (4):151-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Law in Habermas's theory of communicative action.Mathieu Deflem - 1994 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 20 (4):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Law, Morality, and the Existence of Human Rights.Robert Alexy - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (1):2-14.
    In the debate between positivism and non-positivism the argument from relativism plays a pivotal role. The argument from relativism, as put forward, for instance, by Hans Kelsen, says, first, that a necessary connection between law and morality presupposes the existence of absolute, objective, or necessary moral elements, and, second, that no such absolute, objective, or necessary moral elements exist. My reply to this is that absolute, objective, or necessary moral elements do exist, for human rights exist, and human rights exist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Entre arbitrariedad y razonabilidad. Hacia una teoría crítica del neoconstitucionalismo.Massimo Cuono - 2012 - Eunomía. Revista En Cultura de la Legalidad 2021 (3):44-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Trump's Inducement of America's Banality of Evil.Norman K. Swazo - manuscript
    When political philosopher Hannah Arendt introduced the concept of ‘banality of evil’ she did so in reference to the actions of Germans who appropriated the doctrines of National Socialism “thoughtlessly” and without obvious intentions to do evil. But, Arendt’s description of this phenomenon entails that such banality can be found even in a democracy such as the USA. The relation of law and morality must therefore be unambiguous to defend the rule of law against the rule of men. However, a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Validity, Rule of Recognition and Stability: Revisiting Analytical Concepts from the Law‐Morals Connection.Miguel Álvarez Ortega - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (2):247-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Eugenio Bulygin: una breve semblanza.Julieta A. Rabanos & Alejandro Daniel Calzetta - 2021 - Revista Cubana de Derecho 1 (2):11-22.
    El presente texto trata de ofrecer una breve semblanza de la figura de Eugenio Bulygin, reconocido académico y teórico del derecho, fallecido el pasado 11 de mayo de 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Interchangeability of Perspectives Between the Victim and the Offender as an Element of Punishment.Bartosz Wojciechowski - 2014 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 27 (2):277-290.
    The aim of this article is to demonstrate that the theory of changes in perspectives allows a different presentation of the problems which arise from a loss of recognition as an element of punishment, particularly in reference to others, the entire structure of the interaction is changed. Communicative conditions of moral discourses assume that every participant of the argumentation process takes place in all spheres of social life and can assume the perspective common to all other participants. The main task (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Necessity of the Interconnection between Law and Morality.George Pavlakos - 2005 - Ratio Juris 18 (1):64-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Positive Law and Systemic Legitimacy: A Comment on Hart and Habermas.Eric W. Orts - 1993 - Ratio Juris 6 (3):245-278.
    The author revisits H. L. A. Hart's theory of positive law and argues for a major qualification to the thesis of the separation of law and morality based on a concept of systemic legitimacy derived from the social theory of Jurgen Habermas. He argues that standards for assessing the degree of systemic legitimacy in modern legal systems can develop through reflective exercise of “critical legality,” a concept coined to parallel Hart's “critical morality,” and an expanded understanding of the “external” and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Derecho, moral y la existencia de los derechos humanos.Robert Alexy - 2013 - Signos Filosóficos 15 (30):153-171.
    En el debate entre el positivismo y el no-positivismo el argumento del relativismo tiene un papel fundamental. Tal y como es presentado, por ejemplo, por Hans Kelsen, este argumento señala, en primer lugar, que una conexión necesaria entre el derecho y la moral presupone la existencia de elementos morales objetivos, absolutos y necesarios, y, en segundo lugar, que estos elementos morales objetivos, absolutos y necesarios no existen. Mi respuesta a esto es que los elementos morales absolutos, objetivos y necesarios existen, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neil MacCormick's Second Thoughts on Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory. A Defence of the Original View.Aldo Schiavello - 2011 - Ratio Juris 24 (2):140-155.
    This paper offers a diachronic reconstruction of MacCormick's theory of law and legal argumentation: In particular, two related points will be highlighted in which the difference between the perspective upheld in Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory and the later writings is particularly marked. The first point concerns MacCormick's gradual break with legal positivism, and more specifically the thesis that the implicit pretension to justice of law proves legal positivism false in all its different versions. The second point concerns MacCormick's acceptance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Discourse Ethics and the Legitimacy of Law.Kaarlo Tuori - 1989 - Ratio Juris 2 (2):125-143.
    The reconstructive theory of the procedural legitimacy of modern law developed on the basis of the theory of discourse ethics has limited itself solely to the deontological, moral‐normative aspects of the validity claims of legal norms and judgments. However, teleological and axiological aspects are also intertwined with legal validity claims and with the procedures in which legal norms and judgments are produced. The discursive‐procedural concept of legitimacy seems to require as its support, instead of the theory of discourse ethics, a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Empathy, not Truth: Can a Dialectical and Skeptical Argumentation Enhance Both Democracy and Human Rights Courts?Alberto Puppo - 2018 - Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 50 (149):89-117.
    Who is the best moral reasoner, the judge or the legislator? The aim of this paper is to refine this question, by distinguishing between different metaethical assumptions. If the meta-ethical assumptions of arguers are incompatible or if their institutional goal is to establish some truth, there is no way of entering in a constructive argumentative activity. My claim is that only when arguers renounce any epistemic temptation and feel empathy with respect to others’ arguments, can institutions improve the quality of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark