Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Drones, courage, and military culture.Robert Sparrow - 2015 - In Jr Lucas, Routledge Handbook of Military Ethics. London: Routledge. pp. 380-394.
    In so far as long-range tele-operated weapons, such as the United States’ Predator and Reaper drones, allow their operators to fight wars in what appears to be complete safety, thousands of kilometres removed from those whom they target and kill, it is unclear whether drone operators either require courage or have the opportunity to develop or exercise it. This chapter investigates the implications of the development of tele-operated warfare for the extent to which courage will remain central to the role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Performance-enhancing technologies and moral responsibility in the military.Jessica Wolfendale - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (2):28 – 38.
    New scientific advances have created previously unheard of possibilities for enhancing combatants' performance. Future war fighters may be smarter, stronger, and braver than ever before. If these technologies are safe, is there any reason to reject their use? In this article, I argue that the use of enhancements is constrained by the importance of maintaining the moral responsibility of military personnel. This is crucial for two reasons: the military's ethical commitments require military personnel to be morally responsible agents, and moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Collective Military Virtues.Per Sandin - 2007 - Journal of Military Ethics 6 (4):303-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • War without virtue?Robert Sparrow - 2013 - In Bradley Jay Strawser, Killing by Remote Control: The Ethics of an Unmanned Military. New York, US: Oup Usa. pp. 84-105.
    A number of recent and influential accounts of military ethics have argued that there exists a distinctive “role morality” for members of the armed services—a “warrior code.” A “good warrior” is a person who cultivates and exercises the “martial” or “warrior” virtues. By transforming combat into a “desk job” that can be conducted from the safety of the home territory of advanced industrial powers without need for physical strength or martial valour, long-range robotic weapons, such as the “Predator” and “Reaper” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Developing Good Soldiers: The Problem of Fragmentation Within the Army.Paul T. Berghaus & Nathan L. Cartagena - 2013 - Journal of Military Ethics 12 (4):287-303.
    As social creatures, human beings possess a number of identities. A young woman, for example, is a daughter and a member of a particular ethnic group. She is also likely to be a citizen, a friend,...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Response to open Peer commentaries on “performance-enhancing technologies and moral responsibility in the military”.Jessica Wolfendale - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (2):W4 – W6.
    New scientific advances have created previously unheard of possibilities for enhancing combatants' performance. Future war fighters may be smarter, stronger, and braver than ever before. If these technologies are safe, is there any reason to reject their use? In this article, I argue that the use of enhancements is constrained by the importance of maintaining the moral responsibility of military personnel. This is crucial for two reasons: the military's ethical commitments require military personnel to be morally responsible agents, and moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hybrid ethics and the good soldier: the challenge of grounding military ethical thinking and education.Andrew P. Rebera - forthcoming - International Journal of Ethics Education:1-18.
    Military ethics education programmes must prepare soldiers and other military personnel to carry out their duties responsibly, honourably and, above all, ethically. But the practical, moral, and ethical reasoning employed by soldiers in their professional activities—what I call ‘military ethical thinking’—is deeply challenging. The successful interpretation and application of principles and other demands of military ethical thinking presupposes more fundamental commitments that serve as its grounding. But whether soldiers address questions of grounding in their training and education tends to depend (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark